Skip navigation

Journal of Const Law the Court and Press Freedom 2009

Download original document:
Brief thumbnail
This text is machine-read, and may contain errors. Check the original document to verify accuracy.
NEWSGATHERING, AUTONOMY, AND THE SPECIAL-RIGHTS
APOCRYPHA: SUPREME COURT AND MEDIA LITIGANT
CONCEPTIONS OF PRESS FREEDOM
Erik Ugland∗
INTRODUCTION
A few weeks after the U.S. Supreme Court’s 1979 decision in Her1
bert v. Lando, in which the Court refused to prohibit libel plaintiffs
2
from inquiring about journalists’ editorial processes, Justice William
Brennan delivered his renowned address at Rutgers University in
3
which he proposed two models for evaluating free-press cases. Brennan’s speech immediately entered the pantheon of First Amendment
theory, but it was just as remarkable for its cold critique of the news
media and their advocates whom Brennan flayed for their hyperbolic
responses to some of the Court’s press rulings. He scoffed at a Los
Angeles Times editorial suggesting that Herbert would lead to “Orwel4
lian invasion[s] of the mind,” and he chided Jack Landau, then head
of the Reporters Committee for Freedom of the Press, for his overheated claim that Herbert would destroy the press’s “last constitutional
shred of . . . editorial privacy and independence from the govern5
6
ment.” Brennan was an unlikely critic of the press, but he was just
∗

1
2

3

4
5

Assistant Professor, J. William and Mary Diederich College of Communication, Marquette
University. B.A. 1991, University of Minnesota; J.D. 1995, University of Minnesota; M.A.
1999, University of Minnesota; Ph.D. 2002, University of Minnesota.
441 U.S. 153 (1979).
Id. at 160 (holding that it would be unreasonable to prohibit plaintiffs from inquiring
about what the defendant knew and discussed prior to publication because libel plaintiffs
must prove that the defendant acted with some degree of fault).
William J. Brennan, Jr., Assoc. Justice, U.S. Supreme Court, Newhouse Dedication Address (Oct. 17, 1979), in 5 MEDIA L. REP. 1837, 1838 (1980) (“Under one model—which I
call the ‘speech’ model—the press requires and is accorded the absolute protection of
the First Amendment. In the other model—I call it the ‘structural’ model—the press’ interests may conflict with other societal interests and adjustment of the conflict on occasion favors the competing claim.”).
Id. at 1841 (quoting Assoc. Press, Editors, Broadcasters Warn of ‘Chilling Effect’ of Court Ruling, L.A. TIMES, Apr. 19, 1979, at B16).
Id. (quoting TIMES PICAYUNE (New Orleans), Apr. 20, 1979, at 18). Brennan argued that
by permitting libel plaintiffs to inquire into the editorial decision-making of a news organization, the Court was not subjecting journalists to unreasonable examination. In-

375

376

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:2

7

one of a chorus of people who had begun to warn journalists that
their overzealous self-advocacy was eroding the support they had cul8
tivated in the years following Watergate and that by arrogantly staking out an elite social position for themselves and demanding a set of
“special . . . rights” not possessed by the public generally, they were
9
courting a backlash.
Three decades later, the charge of media arrogance and exceptionalism is still at the core of the contemporary American press critique. The news media remain the targets of reprobation in part because the public perceives them as demanding a unique set of legal
10
protections. This is particularly true in the context of the reporter’s
11
12
privilege and the debates over the proposed federal shield law, in

6

7
8

9
10

11

12

quiries into a defendant’s state of mind or intent are common in other areas of the law,
Brennan noted, and to say that journalists should be immune from such inquiries is to
suggest that their minds are “somehow special, and cannot be impinged for any purpose.”
Id. Nevertheless, Brennan appreciated that those kinds of inquiries presented some risks.
He therefore dissented in Herbert to emphasize that while journalists should not be immune from these inquiries, some qualified protection is necessary to minimize the potential for excessive intervention. Herbert, 441 U.S. at 183 (Brennan, J., dissenting).
Brennan was a reliable supporter of the rights of the press and was the author of the
Court’s opinion in New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254 (1964), which is widely regarded as the Court’s most important First Amendment ruling. The Sullivan Court held
that as part of their prima facie libel claims, public official plaintiffs must prove, by clear
and convincing evidence, that the defendant acted “with actual malice—that is, with
knowledge that [their publication] was false or with reckless disregard [for the truth].”
Id. at 279–80.
See infra notes 59–60 and accompanying text.
See David A. Jones, Why Americans Don’t Trust the Media: A Preliminary Analysis, 9 HARV.
INT’L J. PRESS/POL. 60, 61 (2004) (noting that national surveys showed high public support for the press throughout the 1970s).
See William W. Van Alstyne, Comment, The Hazards to the Press of Claiming a “Preferred Position,” 28 HASTINGS L.J. 761, 768 (1977).
See, e.g., Ryan Pitts, Readers Speak: Journalists in Jail, Federal Shield Law, POYNTER ONLINE,
July 23, 2005, http://www.poynter.org/content/content_view.asp?id=85751 (addressing
public opinion about the reporter’s privilege and quoting several respondents, such as
Keith Pennock, who said, “Last time I checked reporters are not a special class of citizen
afforded different rights and privileges than the rest of us.”).
Generally speaking, the reporter’s privilege allows journalists to refuse to comply with
certain subpoenas seeking their testimony or work product. Some form of the privilege is
recognized in most federal jurisdictions, either as a matter of constitutional law, common
law, or administrative procedure. See infra note 18.
In 2007, the U.S. House of Representatives passed a bill (Free Flow of Information Act of
2007, H.R. 2102, 110th Cong. (1st Sess. 2007)) that would establish a federal shield law,
but the Senate did not vote on its version of the bill (Free Flow of Information Act of
2007, S. 1267, 110th Cong. (1st Sess. 2007)) before Congress adjourned.

Jan. 2009]

CONCEPTIONS OF PRESS FREEDOM

377

which journalists’ pleas are frequently dismissed as attempts to posi13
tion themselves as “a priestly class above everybody else.”
This press-public divide has been a central feature of First Amendment litigation over the past thirty five years as the courts have moved
14
beyond issues of expressive freedom. Since Branzburg v. Hayes in
1972, the paramount free-press battles have been less about the dis15
semination of information than its acquisition. In both state and
federal courts, journalists have sought recognition of rights of access
16
to government records and places, protection against certain civil

13

14

15

16

The McLaughlin Group (PBS television broadcast Sept. 1–2, 2007), transcript available at
http://www.mclaughlin.com/library/transcript.htm?id=613. The “priestly class” characterization has been a favorite among critics of the reporter’s privilege. See, e.g., Howard
Kurtz, Contempt & Praise for Reporter: Facing Jail, Judith Miller Gains Support for Stance,
WASH. POST, Feb. 17, 2005, at C1 (quoting the National Review’s Jonah Goldberg as saying, “journalists consider themselves ‘a priestly class’ that doesn’t have to play by the rules
governing ordinary citizens”); Scott MacKay, Plame Takes on Bush Policies in Speech,
PROVIDENCE J., Dec. 5, 2007, at B1 (quoting Valerie (Plame) Wilson as saying, “Journalists
are not a priestly class”). A quarter-century ago, former publisher William Rusher
painted the same portrait. “I object,” Rusher wrote, “to journalists being regarded as a
sort of creeping priesthood, characterized by special powers and limitations—en route,
presumably, to celibacy.” Bulger v. Boston Cmty. Media Council (1976) (Rusher, J., concurring), in IN THE PUBLIC INTEREST III 380 (1979).
408 U.S. 665 (1972). Branzburg considered whether journalists have First Amendment
protection against grand jury subpoenas seeking testimony about their confidential
sources. The Court majority refused to recognize a privilege, but the decisive fifth vote
was supplied by Justice Lewis Powell, who wrote separately to suggest that there might be
situations in which shielding reporters is warranted. Id. at 710 (Powell, J., concurring)
(“In short, the courts will be available to newsmen under circumstances where legitimate
First Amendment interests require protection.”). Powell suggested that courts take a
case-by-case approach to assessing privilege claims. Id.
From the early 1930s through the early 1970s, the Court’s press cases dealt almost exclusively with the constitutionality of direct government restraints on expression. See, e.g.,
Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc., 418 U.S. 323 (1974) (libel); Miami Herald Publ’g Co.v. Tornillo, 418 U.S. 241 (1974) (compelled speech); N.Y. Times Co. v. United States, 403 U.S.
713 (1971) (prior restraints); Time, Inc. v. Hill, 385 U.S. 374 (1966) (privacy); N.Y. Times
Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254 (1964) (libel); Near v. Minnesota ex rel. Olson, 283 U.S. 697
(1931) (prior restraints). In the three decades since Branzburg, the Court has turned
more of its attention to autonomy and newsgathering issues. See, e.g., Cohen v. Cowles
Media Co., 501 U.S. 663 (1991) (protection against enforcement of generally applicable
laws); Richmond Newspapers, Inc. v. Virginia, 448 U.S. 555 (1980) (access to courts);
Herbert v. Lando, 441 U.S. 153 (1979) (protection against inquiries regarding editorial
processes); Houchins v. KQED, Inc., 438 U.S. 1 (1978) (access to prisons); Zurcher v.
Stanford Daily, 436 U.S. 547 (1978) (protection against newsroom searches).
See, e.g., Richmond Newspapers, 448 U.S. at 555 (seeking recognition of a First Amendment
right of access to criminal trials); Nixon v. Warner Commc’ns, Inc., 435 U.S. 589 (1978)
(seeking access to judicial records); Saxbe v. Wash. Post Co., 417 U.S. 843 (1974) (seeking recognition of a First Amendment right of access to federal prisons).

378

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:2
17

and criminal penalties triggered by their newsgathering activity, and
protection against government interference with their source rela18
19
tionships, among other things. They have also fought for statutory
protection from both Congress and state legislatures, particularly on
those issues, and in those jurisdictions, where the courts have been
20
less solicitous. Despite some important successes, many of these efforts have been derailed by judges and lawmakers who bristle at the
idea of endowing journalists with additional immunities, particularly
when more than one-third of Americans say the press already has
21
“too much freedom.”

17

18

19

20

21

See, e.g., United States v. Matthews, 209 F.3d 338 (4th Cir. 2000) (holding that the First
Amendment does not protect journalists when they engage in illegal conduct); Food
Lion, Inc. v. Capital Cities/ABC, Inc., 194 F.3d 505 (4th Cir. 1999) (holding that journalists enjoy no special immunity from tort claims arising out of their newsgathering behavior).
Because Branzburg was essentially a 4.5 to 4.5 decision, see discussion supra note 14, lower
federal courts were free to recognize a privilege in cases dissimilar to those at issue in
Branzburg. As a result, several circuits have recognized at least a qualified privilege. See In
re Madden, 151 F.3d 125 (3d Cir. 1998); United States v. Smith, 135 F.3d 963 (5th Cir.
1998); Shoen v. Shoen, 5 F.3d 1289 (9th Cir. 1993); In re Shain, 978 F.2d 850 (4th Cir.
1992); United States v. LaRouche Campaign, 841 F.2d 1176 (1st Cir. 1988); von Bulow v.
von Bulow, 811 F.2d 136 (2d Cir. 1987); United States v. Caporale, 806 F.2d 1487 (11th
Cir. 1986). Two circuits have explicitly rejected the privilege. See McKevitt v. Pallasch,
339 F.3d 530 (7th Cir. 2003); In re Grand Jury Proceedings, 810 F.2d 580 (6th Cir. 1987).
Other courts have recognized varying levels of protection under the First Amendment,
state constitutions, state or federal common law, or state and federal administrative procedures. In addition, thirty-three states and the District of Columbia have enacted shield
laws that provide explicit statutory protection. See generally Reporters Comm. for Freedom
of the Press, Privilege Compendium, http://www.rcfp.org/privilege/index.php (last visited Jan. 15, 2009). Congress has also considered, but has not yet passed, a federal shield
law. See supra note 12.
See, e.g., Cohen, 501 U.S. at 665 (rejecting journalists’ pleas for First Amendment protection against a civil promissory estoppel suit arising out of the journalists’ breach of confidentiality agreements with source).
The most notable are the press victories in a line of court-access cases in the 1980s. See
Press-Enter. v. Super. Ct., 478 U.S. 1, 10 (1986) (recognizing right of access to transcripts
of preliminary hearings in criminal cases); Press-Enter. v. Super. Ct., 464 U.S. 501, 510
(1984) (recognizing right of access to voir dire in criminal cases); Globe Newspaper Co.
v. Super. Ct., 457 U.S. 596, 610–11 (1982) (striking down state law that peremptorily
closed courtrooms in which minors would be testifying in sexual assault cases); Richmond
Newspapers, 448 U.S. at 580 (recognizing First Amendment right to attend criminal trials).
Also significant are journalists’ successes in reporter’s privilege cases in the lower federal
courts. See supra note 18.
First Amendment Center, ’07 Survey Shows Americans’ Views Mixed on Basic Freedoms,
(Sept. 24, 2007), http://www.firstamendmentcenter.org/news.aspx?id=19031 (noting
that 34% of respondents say the press has “too much” freedom, 50% say it has about the
right amount of freedom, and only 13% say it has “too little” freedom). In this annual
survey, those saying the press has “too much” freedom peaked at 53% in 1999. Id.

Jan. 2009]

CONCEPTIONS OF PRESS FREEDOM

379

There are three key assumptions that have long pervaded these
critiques and that have misdirected many of the judicial, scholarly,
and popular assessments. One is that the press has, in fact, sought to
22
secure for itself a special menu of legal protections. The second is
that the Supreme Court and the media litigants have proposed diametric frameworks—both theoretical and doctrinal—for the resolution of free-press controversies, particularly those relating to newsgathering. And the third is that the Court has largely settled the core
questions surrounding the rights of the press, making these subse23
quent legal maneuvers by journalists all the more gratuitous. Each
of these assumptions is substantially false, and each continues to play
a role in undermining the rights of all people to gather and disseminate news.
This Article addresses the validity of these assumptions by examin24
ing the briefs filed by media litigants in First Amendment cases
brought before the Supreme Court between the 1971–72 term and
the 2006–07 term, as well as the opinions of the Court (majority, con25
curring, and dissenting) in those cases. This Article seeks to validate, refute, or clarify longstanding beliefs about the Court’s rulings
and rationales by evaluating eighty of its media cases. It also provides
the first systematic evaluation of the aims and tactics of the media litigants, along with the frameworks they advanced in their briefs to the
Court in these cases. This is useful not only to satisfy historical curiosities, but also to inform the ongoing public and judicial debates
26
over the scope of press freedom and the right to gather news. These
27
debates are as robust as ever, but they will not be productive if they
are oriented around specious assumptions about the Court’s freepress jurisprudence. And to the extent that the participants misun22
23

24
25
26
27

See, e.g., Adam Liptak, Courts Grow Increasingly Skeptical of Any Special Protections for the Press,
N.Y. TIMES, June 28, 2005, at A16.
See Michael Battle, No Special Privilege, USA TODAY, June 22, 2006, at A12 (“The law is
clear. The U.S. Supreme Court declined to interpret the First Amendment to grant
newsmen a testimonial privilege that other citizens do not enjoy.” (internal quotation
marks omitted)); see also Steve Chapman, The News Media vs. The Innocent, CHI. TRIB., Mar.
27, 2008 (calling journalists who invoke the reporter’s privilege “slow learners about the
obligations they share with their fellow citizens” for defying the court).
In all cases before the Court, both petitioners and respondents must file a brief outlining
their case and explaining why the Court should rule in their favor.
For more on the criteria applied to the selection of cases, see infra Part II.
Indeed, the two are intertwined in the sense that the flawed conventional wisdom continues to shape the way the public perceives the press’s claims.
For example, the Journal of Mass Media Ethics devoted its entire Fall 2007 issue to this question. See also JAY ROSEN, WHAT ARE JOURNALISTS FOR? (2001); Gina Barton, What Is a
Jour·na·list?, QUILL MAG., May 2002, at 10.

380

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:2

derstand the objectives and arguments of the media litigants, any potential points of concurrence will likely be lost in the fog of anti-press
rhetoric.
The broader aim of this Article is to provide fodder for those who
hope to establish some theoretical and doctrinal congruity in this
28
area of law. This has to start with a clear understanding of the
Court’s decisions and the principles that animate them, and it can
also be advanced by reexamining the arguments of the media litigants to see if they provide a more cogent construction.
The results of this analysis show, among other things, that the
media litigants have not sought recognition of special rights or proposed a framework that distinguishes between mainstream and more
peripheral media. Indeed, they have been more diligent than the
Court in avoiding references and arguments that separate speech and
press and that imply the need for unusual scrutiny of restraints targeting media defendants. The litigants have also more consistently
29
championed an “egalitarian” conception of the press that recognizes
the ability and right of all citizens to seek and disseminate news. The
Court, meanwhile, has misconceived the nature of special rights, it
has falsely accused the media litigants of seeking such rights, and it
has relied on a conventional conception of the press that belies the
30
“lonely pamphleteer” archetype it idealized in Branzburg v. Hayes.
Part I of this Article provides an overview of the central arguments
made by those opposed to recognition of expansive press and newsgathering rights, and it also addresses the consequences of those critiques. Part II describes the key research questions and explains the
rationale for the selection of cases and briefs examined here. Part III
presents the results of the analyses of the Court’s opinions and media
litigant briefs. Part IV contains the conclusions and recommendations.

28

29

30

C. Edwin Baker makes the same plea suggesting that, in the absence of normative clarity,
the courts will inevitably produce conflicting decisions. See C. Edwin Baker, The Independent Significance of the Press Clause under Existing Law, 35 HOFSTRA L. REV. 955, 1024 (2007)
(“The Court and the law should get it right!”).
Erik Ugland & Jennifer Henderson, Who Is a Journalist and Why Does it Matter? Disentangling the Legal and Ethical Arguments, 22 J. MASS MEDIA ETHICS 241, 246–47 (2007) (distinguishing an egalitarian model of the press from an expert model of the press); see also infra note 93 and accompanying text.
408 U.S. 665, 704 (1972) (“[L]iberty of the press is the right of the lonely pamphleteer
who uses carbon paper or a mimeograph just as much as of the large metropolitan publisher . . . .”).

Jan. 2009]

CONCEPTIONS OF PRESS FREEDOM

381

I. CONTEMPORARY AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT
31

The law of newsgathering is a patchwork of conflicting case law,
appended by an assortment of statutes that, in some cases, provide
32
journalists with special dispensations. The absence of uniformity is
partly a consequence of the infirmities in the Supreme Court’s First
Amendment jurisprudence and its indefinite rulings in free-press
33
cases ; more immediately, it is the result of the lower courts’ willing34
ness to supply their own doctrine, and of journalists’ persistence in
35
lobbying for legislative accommodations.
This fractured legal landscape mirrors, and is partly the product
of, the broader divisions between the press and the courts. Each has
some legitimate grievances against the other, but each is also occasionally guilty of mischaracterizing the other’s honest efforts. Some
journalists are quick to demonize those who doubt their need for
protection and to catastrophize the effects of unfavorable court rul36
ings. At the same time, judges and public critics too often misperceive journalists’ legal claims as acts of self-aggrandizement rather
than as sincere attempts to vindicate the rights of all citizens to be, as
37
the Framers put it, “bulwarks of liberty.”
31
32
33
34

35

36

37

See generally Erik Ugland, Demarcating the Right to Gather News: A Sequential Interpretation of
the First Amendment, 3 DUKE J. CONST. L. & PUB. POL’Y 101 (2008).
See infra note 35.
See infra Parts III.A.1, III.B.1, III.C.1.
The law of reporter’s privilege, for example, is defined as much by federal circuit court
decisions—many of which recognize some protection for reporters’ sources and work
product—as it is by the Court’s opinion in Branzburg. See supra note 18.
In addition to the dozens of state shield laws that have been passed in the wake of Branzburg, see supra note 18, journalists have: (1) secured protections against some news room
searches, e.g., Privacy Protection Act, 42 U.S.C. § 2000aa(a) (2000); (2) successfully lobbied for retraction statutes that limit plaintiff’s libel suits targeting media defendants, e.g.,
WIS. STAT. § 895.05 (2008); and (3) secured exemptions from some of the fees normally
charged for records requests under state and federal open records statutes, e.g., The
Freedom of Information Act, 5 U.S.C. § 552(a)(4)(A)(ii) (2006) (“[F]ees shall be limited
to reasonable standard charges . . . when records are not sought for commercial use and
the request is made by . . . a representative of the news media . . . .”).
See, e.g., Cathy Packer, Op-Ed., What Became of the First Amendment?, NEWS & OBSERVER,
Oct. 25, 2007, at A11 (calling the spate of journalist subpoenas “the most vicious and calculated attack on the free press in America since the Nixon administration”); see also Jack
Shafer,
First
Amendment
Chicken
Little,
SLATE,
Dec.
17,
2004,
http://www.slate.com/id/=2111206/ (criticizing Washington Post columnist E.J. Dionne
and others for overreacting to journalist subpoenas).
This phrase was commonly repeated by patriot printers and was included in James Madison’s first draft of the First Amendment. See David A. Anderson, The Origins of the Press
Clause, 30 UCLA L. REV. 455, 478 (1983). The phrase was originally drawn from Cato’s
Letters. See John Trenchard & Thomas Gordon, Of Freedom of Speech: That the Same is Inseparable from Publick Liberty, in 1 CATO’S LETTERS; OR ESSAYS ON LIBERTY, CIVIL AND

382

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:2

It is certainly reasonable for judges to be concerned about bestowing special protections on the press. Doing so could disrupt the
38
“ethos of equality” that pervades the Constitution, and it could initiate some doctrinal creep toward the unsteady world of situational
balancing. Journalists, meanwhile, have their own valid concerns.
Their constitutional and statutory protections are increasingly frag39
ile—some say “under assault” —in a post-September 11th environment in which judges have shown impatience with many rights-based
40
claims. In just the past few years, dozens of journalists have been
41
subpoenaed in civil and criminal cases, several have been held in
42
contempt, and a few have been sent to jail for refusing to expose
43
their confidential sources.

38
39

40

41

42

43

RELIGIOUS, AND OTHER IMPORTANT SUBJECTS 96, 100 (1733) (“Freedom of Speech is the
great Bulwark of Liberty; they prosper and die together . . . .”).
See Ugland, supra note 31, at 149.
See, e.g., Jessica Meyers, Fighting Like Tigers: A Conference Explores How to Protect Sources in a
Hostile Legal and Political Climate, AM. JOURNALISM REV., June/July 2006, at 58 (“The journalist-source relationship so essential to investigative reporting has come under assault.”).
For a series of reports concerning the way judges have handled rights-based claims, see
Reporters Comm. for Freedom of the Press, Secret Justice, http://rcfp.org/secretjustice/
(last visited Jan. 15, 2009).
New York Times reporter James Risen was recently subpoenaed by a grand jury to identify
confidential sources for his book State of War. See Philip Shenon, Times Reporter Subpoenaed
Over Source for Book Chapter, N.Y. TIMES, Feb. 1, 2008, at A17. Risen is just one of dozens
who have been subpoenaed in the past few years. Fifteen reporters have been subpoenaed in the Privacy Act suit filed by Dr. Steven Hatfill who claims the government falsely
accused him of being behind the anthrax attacks in New York and Washington, D.C., five
reporters have been subpoenaed in the grand jury investigation of the BALCO laboratory, and eight reporters have been subpoenaed in the ongoing federal investigation into
illegal leaks at the White House. For a more complete account of these and other cases,
see Reporters Comm. for Freedom of the Press, Shields and Subpoenas: The Reporter’s
Privilege in Federal Courts, http://www.rcfp.org/shields_and_subpoenas.html#number
(last visited Jan. 15, 2009).
Most recently, U.S. District Court Judge Reggie Walton held former USA Today reporter
Toni Locy in contempt for refusing to identify her confidential sources in Dr. Steven Hatfill’s Privacy Act suit. Torsten Ove, Ex-Reporter Put in Tough Spot in Fight Over Sources,
PITTSBURGH POST-GAZETTE, Mar. 16, 2008, at A1.
Video blogger Josh Wolf spent more than seven months in jail (the longest time ever
served by a journalist in a contempt case) for refusing to comply with a subpoena seeking
his testimony and video footage about a violent protest that he had covered. His attempts
to quash the subpoena failed and his appeal was denied on September 8, 2006. In re
Grand Jury Subpoena, 201 F. App’x 430 (9th Cir. 2006). Wolf was released after reaching
an agreement with prosecutors to post his video footage on his Weblog. Reporters
Comm. for Freedom of the Press, Blogger Released from Prison, Apr. 4, 2007,
http://rcfp.org/news/2007/0404-con-blogge.html. Former New York Times reporter Judith Miller spent eighty-five days in jail in 2005 for refusing to identity the source who
leaked the name of undercover CIA agent, Valerie (Plame) Wilson, to her. Her appeal of
the contempt charge was rejected. In re Grand Jury Subpoena, 397 F.3d 964 (D.C. Cir.
2005). Television reporter Jim Taricani was confined at home for six months for refusing

Jan. 2009]

383

CONCEPTIONS OF PRESS FREEDOM
44

In other cases, journalists have had their phone records seized or
45
their mail confiscated. Journalists have been denied access to places
and records that have traditionally been part of their reportorial do46
mains, and they still have no significant protection against civil suits
47
targeting their newsgathering activity.
Journalists’ efforts to preserve or restore these protections have
48
49
50
been met with suspicion from citizen-critics, judges, lawyers, poli51
52
53
ticians, constitutional scholars, and even some journalists. Vet-

44

45

46

47

48
49

50
51

52

to identify a confidential source in a story he produced about government corruption.
William Ketter, Law Might Be Bad News for Press Freedom, JOURNAL-GAZETTE (Fort Wayne,
Ind.), July 17, 2008, at 11A. And in 2001–2002, freelance author Vanessa Leggett was
held in contempt and served 168 days in jail for refusing to turn over tapes of interviews
she had conducted with witnesses whom prosecutors believed had information relevant to
a murder investigation. Reporters Comm. for Freedom of the Press, Vanessa Leggett Released from Jail after 168 Days (Jan. 4, 2002), http://www.rcfp.org/news/releases/
view.php?2002_01_04_vlreleas.txt.
In 2004, U.S. Attorney Patrick Fitzgerald seized the phone records of two New York Times
reporters in order to learn the identities of their confidential sources. N.Y. Times Co. v.
Gonzalez, 459 F.3d 160, 165 (2d Cir. 2006). The reporters’ challenge to the seizure was
subsequently rejected. Id. at 174. More recently, police in St. Paul seized the cell phone
records of KMSP-TV (Minneapolis) reporter Tom Lyden in order to uncover the identity
of one of his sources. Mara H. Gottfried, Police Return Reporter’s Records, ST. PAUL PIONEER
PRESS, Dec. 19, 2007.
In 2003, a package sent by one Associated Press reporter in the Philippines to a co-worker
in the United States was intercepted and confiscated by the FBI, even though the seized
document was from a public record. Associated Press, FBI Returns Lab Report to News Service, May 11, 2003, available at http://www.firstamendmentcenter.org/news.aspx?id=
11455.
For example, reporters are barred from Dover Air Force Base, where the bodies of American troops killed abroad are returned to the United States. See Brian Faler, Rules Change
on Seeing Troops’ Remains Return: Families May See Caskets’ Removal from Planes, WASH. POST,
June 24, 2004, at A18 (noting that while this policy went into effect in 1991, it was not
consistently enforced until after the start of the Iraq War).
The most significant case in this area is Food Lion, Inc. v. Capital Cities/ABC, Inc., 194 F.3d
505 (4th Cir. 1999), holding that journalists are not protected from civil claims, such as
fraud or trespass, triggered by their newsgathering activity, even though they are protected against damage awards related to their subsequent publication or broadcast.
See supra note 10.
See, e.g., McKevitt v. Pallasch, 339 F.3d 530, 533 (7th Cir. 2003) (“We do not see why there
need to be special criteria merely because the possessor of the documents or other evidence sought is a journalist.” (emphasis added)).
See supra note 23.
See, e.g., Elizabeth Williamson, House Passes Bill to Protect Confidentiality of Reporters’ Sources,
WASH. POST, Oct. 17, 2007, at A3 (“Rep. Lamar Smith (Tex.), ranking Republican on the
House Judiciary Committee, opposed the [federal shield bill], echoing Justice Department concerns that ‘this legislation will impede its efforts to conduct its investigations
and prosecute criminals’ and adding: ‘No one should be above the law, not even the
press.’”).
See, e.g., Randall D. Eliason, Leakers, Bloggers, and Fourth Estate Inmates: The Misguided Pursuit of a Reporter’s Privilege, 24 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 385, 386 (2007) (questioning the

384

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:2

eran New York Times reporter Anthony Lewis is a longtime opponent
of reporter’s privilege and says its recognition would only “add[] to
the already evident public feeling that the press thinks it is entitled to
54
special treatment.” He added at a 2007 meeting of media lawyers
that “[j]ournalists shouldn’t act [as if] their rights are always superior
55
to those of others.” The critics have reserved their most biting attacks for those journalists who have gone to jail to protect their
sources. University of Chicago law professor Geoffrey Stone accuses
these reporters of seeking martyrdom: “It is undoubtedly great drama. But where does a reporter get off insisting that he is above the
56
law, the Congress, the Supreme Court, and the Constitution?”
These comments are typical in that they assume the law is clear,
57
which it is not, and that journalists have in fact sought truly special
58
rights, which, for the most part, they have not. Nevertheless, these
arguments have been repeated ad nauseam for decades. Twentyeight years ago, constitutional scholar Ronald Dworkin accused the
press of viewing the First Amendment as “a kind of private charter,
and attack[ing] more or less automatically every refusal of the courts
59
to find some further protection in that charter.” And in 1979, former National Review publisher, William Rusher complained about
what he called a “brand-new bid by an aggressive and highly politicalized press for privileges and immunities which it has never previously
had, which it neither needs nor deserves, and which it would be dan60
gerous to confer upon it.” Arguments like these were sometimes

53

54

55
56

57
58
59
60

“social utility” of reporter’s privilege); Kara A. Larsen, Note, The Demise of the First Amendment-Based Reporter’s Privilege: Why this Current Trend Should Not Surprise the Media, 37 CONN.
L. REV. 1235 (2005) (examining the evolution of reporter’s privilege).
See, e.g., Anthony Lewis, Privilege & the Press, N.Y. REV. BOOKS, July 14, 2005 (reviewing
FLOYD ABRAMS, SPEAKING FREELY: TRIALS OF THE FIRST AMENDMENT (2005)) (arguing that
the press should only have qualified privilege, not absolute privilege).
Id. Lewis made this same basic argument about the lack of public support for the press
being “constitutionally unique” three decades ago. Anthony Lewis, A Preferred Position for
Journalism?, 7 HOFSTRA L. REV. 595, 609 (1979).
Anthony Lewis, Address at the Communications Law Conference of the Practising Law
Institute (Nov. 8, 2007).
Paul McMasters & Geoffrey R. Stone, Debate Club: Do Journalists Need a Better Shield?, LEGAL
AFFAIRS, Dec. 6, 2004, http://www.legalaffairs.org/webexclusive/dc_printerfriendly.
msp?id=21.
There are many people who still contend, for example, that Branzburg settled the question of reporter’s privilege. See supra note 23.
See infra Part III.B.2.
Ronald Dworkin, Is the Press Losing the First Amendment?, N.Y. REV. BOOKS, Dec. 4, 1980, at
49.
William Rusher, Statement on the Press and the Courts, in NATIONAL NEWS COUNCIL, IN THE
PUBLIC INTEREST II 353 (1979).

Jan. 2009]

CONCEPTIONS OF PRESS FREEDOM

385

aimed less at individual journalists than at advocacy groups like the
61
Reporters Committee for Freedom of the Press, but it was often as62
sumed that they shared the same vision. Indeed, the notion still
persists that journalists are a kind of united brotherhood of professionals who all read from the same script on press freedom.
Some critics have focused their attacks on mainstream or traditional journalists whom they accuse of trying to appropriate the First
Amendment for their own purposes while denying it to those who
63
lack their professional pedigree.
Certainly some journalists have
sought to distinguish their practices and standards from those of
64
other communicators, but it is uncommon for them to suggest that
the First Amendment be construed to provide additional protections
65
to those in the higher echelons of their field. Nevertheless, the
abiding assumption since Branzburg has been that the institutional
media have sought special rights for themselves, and that in order to
secure those protections, they have constructed “novel and strained
interpretations of [the] First and Fourteenth Amendments to the
66
Constitution.” The most significant of these is the notion that the
67
68
Speech Clause and Press Clause be interpreted as having constitutionally discrete meanings. Justice Potter Stewart is the intellectual
architect of this framework, which he outlined in a 1975 speech at
61
62

63

64

65

66

67
68

Indeed, Brennan’s Rutgers address seems to target press advocates as much as journalists
themselves. See supra note 3.
Media lawyer Cameron DeVore said “[t]he Reporters Committee [under Jack Landau]
was strident and sometimes off-putting to owners, and its legal ideas were not always in
tune with the attorneys it called upon.” Floyd J. McKay, First Amendment Guerillas: Formative Years of the Reporters Committee for Freedom of the Press, JOURNALISM & COMM.
MONOGRAPHS, Autumn 2004, at 107, 125. Jane Kirtley, Landau’s successor, added: “It
wasn’t so much that we were troubled by Jack expressing an opinion, a point of view; the
problem was that in some quarters he was perceived to speak for the media.” Id. at 132.
Matt Welch, Why Does Old Media Trash the New?, ONLINE JOURNALISM REV., June 24, 1998,
http://www.ojr.org/ojr/ethics/1017968389.php (discussing the views of mainstream media towards Internet-based media).
See Clarence Page, Who’s a Journalist?, ONLINE NEWSHOUR, June 7, 2005,
http://www.pbs.org/newshour/essays/jan-june05/page_6-7.html (discussing who constitutes a journalist).
Indeed, many mainstream journalists also operate blogs, and many full-time bloggers
once worked for traditional news organizations. See Jessi Hempel, Are Bloggers Journalists?,
BUSINESSWEEK, Mar. 7, 2005, http://www.businessweek.com/technology/content/
mar2005/tc2005037_7877_tc024.htm.
William Rusher, supra note 60, at 360. Rusher added that journalists are “embarking on a
new and fateful course . . . to distinguish the media from the people as a whole. In doing
so, they run a grave risk of alienating the public permanently.” Id.
U.S. CONST. amend. I (“Congress shall make no law . . . abridging the freedom of
speech . . . .”).
Id. (“Congress shall make no law . . . abridging the freedom of . . . the press . . . .”).

386

[Vol. 11:2

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW
69

70

Yale Law School. Stewart, who dissented in Branzburg, argued that
while the Speech Clause protects the rights of all citizens to freely express themselves, the Press Clause is a “structural provision” that protects “the institutional autonomy of the press,” which encompasses its
71
confidential relationships with sources, among other things.
72
This construction of the First Amendment was widely criticized.
But many critics have incorrectly assumed that those seeking to preserve or augment press freedoms have drawn their inspiration from
Stewart; that they have used his model as the theoretical foundation
for their legal arguments before the courts, and, perhaps most importantly, that they have embraced Stewart’s narrow definition of
“the press,” which encompassed only the “daily newspapers and other
73
established news media.” The remainder of this Article shows that
none of these claims has any validity with respect to the arguments
made by the litigants in their briefs, and that the Court itself, by repeatedly and inappropriately using the special-rights aspersion to discredit the media litigants’ claims, has probably contributed as much
as any party to the persistent misunderstandings about the litigants’
aims and the legitimacy of their constitutional arguments. The
Court’s own free-press jurisprudence, meanwhile, is ambiguous and
contradictory and provides a far less stable model for resolving freepress controversies than the one reflected in the litigants’ briefs.
II. CENTRAL QUESTIONS AND SCOPE OF ANALYSIS
There are three general questions that have defined this debate
since Branzburg and that are still constitutionally salient: (1) Does the
Press Clause have a meaning independent of the Speech Clause? (2)
Does the Constitution endow journalists, “the press,” or subsets of
69
70

71
72

73

Potter Stewart, Or of the Press, 26 HASTINGS L.J. 631 (1975).
Branzburg v. Hayes, 408 U.S. 665, 743 (1972) (Stewart, J., dissenting) (arguing that before a journalist could be made to comply with a subpoena, the government ought to be
forced to: “(1) show . . . probable cause to believe that the newsman has information that
is clearly relevant to a specific probable violation of law; (2) demonstrate that the information sought cannot be obtained by alternative means . . . ; and (3) demonstrate a compelling and overriding interest in the information.” (footnote omitted)).
Stewart, supra note 69, at 633–34 (emphasis omitted).
See, e.g., Lewis, supra note 53, at 597 (disagreeing with the notion of a preferred status for
journalists); Robert D. Sack, Reflections on the Wrong Question: Special Constitutional Privilege
for the Institutional Press, 7 HOFSTRA L. REV. 629, 629 (1979) (arguing that the “ultimate
question” is “whether the press’ legal protection is adequate to enable it to perform its
role properly”); Van Alstyne, supra note 9, at 769 (arguing that the Free Press Clause only
gives the press equal freedom of speech protection as an individual).
Stewart, supra note 69, at 631.

Jan. 2009]

CONCEPTIONS OF PRESS FREEDOM

387

these entities, with special rights not possessed by the public generally? And (3) Who is a journalist and what is “the press”? There is
still some misunderstanding about the Court’s responses to these
questions, not to mention some dissatisfaction with its answers.
Meanwhile, the arguments presented by the media litigants have
never been systematically studied but are important to examine, both
to assess the validity of the criticisms that have been aimed at them,
and to mine for insights in the ongoing effort to construct a constitutionally sound framework for defining the scope of press freedom
74
and the right to gather news.
The findings and analysis are presented below in three subsections corresponding to the general questions above. The first section
looks at whether the Court or media litigants have made references
to particular clauses of the First Amendment and whether they concluded (or proposed, in the case of the litigants) that the Speech and
Press Clauses be interpreted independently. The second section
looks at whether the Court has provided different levels of freedom
to particular groups or media and whether the media litigants have
sought separate treatment. And the last section looks at how the
Court and litigants have defined the press—either explicitly or by virtue of either the characteristics they emphasize as being journalistic
or the labels they attach to different media.
This Article is focused on the “media” or “press” cases decided by
the Supreme Court between 1971–72 and 2006–07. In selecting the
cases, a Westlaw search was conducted of all Supreme Court cases in
which the phrases “freedom of the press,” “free press,” “press freedom,” “speech and press” or “speech or press” appeared in the case
syllabus, digest, or headnotes. A second search was conducted for all
75
Supreme Court cases reprinted in the Media Law Reporter. These
lists were cross-checked against each other and the combined list was
76
cross-checked against lists used by other scholars in previous studies.

74

75
76

It should be noted that the media litigants’ briefs are not pristine expressions of constitutional argument. They are written, in part, with tactical goals in mind. Nevertheless, litigants still do occasionally propose novel theories and challenge hardened orthodoxies in
their efforts to persuade the Court. In any case, the point of this study is to evaluate assumptions about the arguments made in the briefs, irrespective of the arguments journalists or their advocates have made in other contexts.
This is a case reporter in which nearly all decisions relating to the law of the mass media
are published.
These include ELIZABETH BLANKS HINDMAN, RIGHTS VS. RESPONSIBILITIES: THE SUPREME
COURT AND THE MEDIA at app. (1997), and Thomas Alphonse Schwartz, A Reconceptualization of the First Amendment: The Burger Court and Freedom of the Press, 1969–1980

388

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:2

Applying these search criteria yielded a list of 212 cases. This list
was narrowed by eliminating cases that did not involve a media litigant. “Media” was defined broadly to encompass any medium used
for communicating to a mass audience. This included traditional
outlets, such as radio, television, newspapers, and magazines, but also
underground publications, cable television, and the Internet. Not
every litigant whose speech was expressed through a medium was
considered a media litigant, however. Cases involving demonstrators
using placards or engaging in acts of symbolic speech were not in77
78
cluded, nor were cases involving obscenity or commercial speech.
Also eliminated were cases in which the Court issued only a memo79
randum opinion, or in which no free speech or press issue was pre80
sented. Applying these criteria yielded a final list of eighty cases,
81
with an equal number of media briefs.
III. FINDINGS AND ANALYSIS
This Part contains summaries and analyses of the court opinions
and media litigant briefs, with each subsection addressing one of the
three core questions noted above. Collectively, they also provide a
basis for evaluating some of the common assumptions noted at the
82
outset of the Article that have been made by critics of the media’s
efforts to secure legal protections.
Debates over the meaning of the Speech and Press Clauses of the
First Amendment are often stymied by the parties’ failure to clarify
basic terms and assumptions. There are three essential models, however, that shape most assessments and that are used here to help
frame this analysis. The first is an expression model in which the Speech
and Press Clauses are read together as a collective statement about
the freedom of all citizens to communicate, whether through speech

77
78
79
80
81

82

(May 1981) (unpublished Ph.D. dissertation, Southern Illinois University) (on file with
UMI Dissertation Service).
This was largely a pragmatic choice designed to produce a final list that was manageable
but that did not exclude the most salient cases.
See supra note 77.
Memorandum opinions are official rulings on the merits of a case, but they are not accompanied by a written opinion outlining the Court’s rationale.
The focus here is not on all legal conflicts involving media, but on those cases that shed
light on the scope of speech and press freedom.
Occasionally, more than one media litigant was involved in a case and each party would
contribute its own brief. In those cases, the brief written by the first-named media litigant
was selected. Those briefs tend to be the most comprehensive, with the other briefs often
augmenting and referencing them.
See supra notes 22–23 and accompanying text.

Jan. 2009]

CONCEPTIONS OF PRESS FREEDOM

389

or through media, and in which all citizens have equal standing to invoke those protections. Under this model, the Press Clause has no
meaning independent of the Speech Clause, and no protection is
recognized for newsgathering or other non-expressive acts. The second is an autonomy model in which the Speech Clause is read as protecting free expression while the Press Clause is understood as a
shield against more indirect usurpations of the independence of
83
communicators.
This model provides at least some protection
against, for example, government encroachments into newsrooms or
interference with source relationships, and its protections are available to anyone who seeks to gather and report news. The third approach is a special-rights model, which parallels the autonomy model
except that it reserves the Press Clause protections for those communicators who possess certain professional attributes or institutional affiliations.
A. Speech Clause v. Press Clause
The questions posed in this area were aimed at understanding
what the textual basis has been for the parties’ interpretations of the
Speech and Press Clauses. Specifically, have they interpreted the
clauses independently, or have they evaluated them as expressions of
a single concept? And have the parties explicitly or implicitly en84
dorsed the thesis proposed by Justice Stewart in “Or of the Press”?
85
It is commonly asserted that the Supreme Court has rejected Justice Stewart’s argument that the Speech and Press Clauses were in86
tended to be construed separately. It is true that the Court has neither explicitly endorsed Stewart’s thesis nor tied its rulings to the

83

84
85

86

Another expression of this approach would be to say that the Speech and Press Clauses
have no independent significance and they merely protect expression, but that in order
to protect expression, one must also protect the autonomy of communicators from government actions that can intimidate, harass, or otherwise indirectly inhibit expressive activity.
See Stewart, supra note 69.
See Anthony L. Fargo, The Journalist’s Privilege for Nonconfidential Information in States Without Shield Laws, 7 COMM. L. & POL’Y 241, 252–53 (2002) (observing that the Court’s “majority noted that Congress was free to create a statutory privilege, and the states were free
to recognize a privilege through statutes or through interpretations of their own constitutions”).
See Baker, supra note 28, at 959 (arguing that, although the courts have not explicitly acknowledged such a distinction, an independent meaning for the Press Clause is implicit
in their rulings and that, in any case, it provides a useful construct for resolving free-press
controversies).

390

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:2

87

precise language of either clause. But it is too much to say the
Court’s approach and Stewart’s are wholly incongruent, at least without understanding more clearly what Stewart meant.
Stewart argued that to conjoin the Speech and Press Clauses
88
would create a textual redundancy that the Framers did not intend.
He therefore proposed that the Speech Clause be read as a shield
against government restraints of expression while the Press Clause be
understood as a structural provision designed to protect the press in
89
its institutional role as a watchdog of powerful interests. So when
the government compels reporters to divulge their confidential
sources, for example, it pierces the autonomy of the press and im90
pedes its “constitutional mission,” whether or not there is any immediately measurable effect on its speech.
Stewart’s Yale address seems to provide a blueprint for recognition of special press rights, but it is ambiguous enough to invite a
narrower interpretation. For example, Stewart highlights cases like
91
New York Times Co. v. United States (the Pentagon Papers case) and
92
Miami Herald Publishing Co. v. Tornillo as exemplifying his theory.
But those cases both involved direct government restraints of expression and can be explained by reference to speech principles alone.
The only arguably special-rights case described by Stewart in his Yale
address was Branzburg. But even the reporter’s privilege (despite its
unfortunate name) need not be construed as a special right. Those
who conceive of it in those terms typically have in mind what Ugland
and Henderson call an expert definition of the press—one in which
“journalists are conceived of as a uniquely qualified and clearly identifiable collection of professionals who serve as agents of the public in
93
the procurement and dissemination of news.” But most lower courts
and legislatures have begun to move away from that definition and
toward a more egalitarian definition of the press “in which all citizens
are equally equipped and equally free to serve as newsgathering
87

88
89
90
91
92
93

See infra Part III.A.1. Note, however, that during the middle part of the twentieth century,
the Court did emphasize the Press Clause in some cases. See David A. Anderson, Freedom
of the Press, 80 TEX. L. REV. 429, 448 (2002) (calling the period between the 1930s and the
1960s “the heyday of the Press Clause in the Supreme Court”).
See Stewart, supra note 69, at 633.
Id.
Branzburg v. Hayes, 408 U.S. 665, 729 (1972) (Stewart, J., dissenting).
403 U.S. 713 (1971) (striking down an injunction prohibiting the New York Times from
publishing classified documents obtained by a third party).
418 U.S. 241 (1974) (striking down a Florida statue giving political candidates a right to
reply to their critics in any newspaper).
See Ugland & Henderson, supra note 29, at 246–47.

Jan. 2009]

CONCEPTIONS OF PRESS FREEDOM

391

94

watchdogs.” By protecting the underlying function rather than assigning those protections to a particular group, the special-rights
95
problem is mitigated, if not eliminated. And that is the only definition that seems to be practically and constitutionally workable in an
era in which anyone can disseminate information to a mass audience.
Unfortunately, Stewart is not so easily saved by this construction
because he began his Yale speech by saying he intended to address
96
“the role of the organized press” and he argued later that historically
the press was understood as providing “expert scrutiny of govern97
ment.” Whether Stewart truly intended to limit Press Clause protection to the institutional media is not entirely clear, however, because
his opinions on the Court show no evidence of a desire to confer spe98
cial rights on the press or to define the press in ways that discrimi99
nate between mainstream and more peripheral media. So it could
94
95
96

97
98

99

Id. at 247.
See infra notes 150–52 and accompanying text.
Stewart, supra note 69, at 631 (emphasis added). Stewart later added that the press is “the
only organized private business that is given explicit constitutional protection.” Id. at 633
(emphasis added).
Id. at 634 (emphasis added).
Other than Branzburg, there were only two cases in which Stewart’s opinions could be construed as recognizing special rights, although they need not be interpreted that way. The
first was Zurcher v. Stanford Daily, 436 U.S. 547 (1978), in which Stewart argued in dissent
that a police search of the offices of a college newspaper was unconstitutional. Id. at 571
(Stewart, J., dissenting) (“It seems to me self-evident that police searches of newspaper offices burden the freedom of the press.”). Much like his Branzburg dissent, Stewart’s opinion in Zurcher was rooted in the Press Clause and was built around an autonomy concept
that was attentive to the more subtle ways in which government restrictions on nonexpressive acts could collaterally damage expressive ones. See id. at 570–77. This could be
construed as recognition of a special right in that Stewart was suggesting that the press
status of the searched party would trigger the application of different constitutional standards. Indeed, he described Zurcher as a “press” case. Id. at 571. But it is not clear that
Stewart had in mind a set of rights that would only flow to particular organizations, or if
they would be available to any person or group serving a press function.
The other case was Houchins v. KQED, Inc., 438 U.S. 1 (1978), in which the Court upheld an interlocutory appeal, enjoining a news organization’s attempt to access a federal
prison facility. Stewart wrote a concurring opinion insisting that even in providing the
press with equal access to prisons, some special accommodation must be made for their
use of newsgathering equipment. Id. at 17 (Stewart, J., concurring in judgment)
(“[T]erms of access that are reasonably imposed on individual members of the public
may, if they impede effective reporting without sufficient justification, be unreasonable as
applied to journalists . . . .”). But again, it is not clear that Stewart would have limited
these protections to those in the mainstream media, or if anyone assuming that role and
using those devices would be eligible. In the absence of such statements, one cannot
characterize Stewart as an advocate of a special-rights model, at least not without trying to
tie in the extrajudicial comments from his Yale speech.
Indeed, even his dissent in Branzburg is devoid of the kinds of references to the institutional media found in Or of the Press. Although Stewart, like the Court majority, uses the

392

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:2

be that his Yale speech simply reflected his assumption that in 1974
mainstream journalists were, for all practical purposes, the only people who would ever need these protections.
Although Stewart is perceived to be the key exemplar of the special-rights model and a constitutional pathfinder of sorts for the media litigants, his opinions on the Court actually fit comfortably within
the autonomy model—a framework that the Court majority has itself
embraced on occasion. In Branzburg, for example, the Court acknowledged that “news gathering is not without its First Amendment
100
protections,” and that “without some protection for seeking out the
101
news, freedom of the press could be eviscerated.”
Similarly, in
102
Richmond Newspapers, Inc. v. Virginia, the Court held that the press
and public have a First Amendment right to attend criminal trials, in
part to ensure the fairness of those proceedings, but also to indulge
103
the information-gathering interests of the attendees. So the Court
cannot be characterized as endorsing a pure expression model when
it clearly conceives of the First Amendment as protecting some nonexpressive activity. There are some clear differences between Stewart’s approach and the approach of the Court majority, but it is misleading to present them as entirely incompatible. The same can be
said of the relationship between the Court and the media litigants.
1. U.S. Supreme Court
The Supreme Court has routinely acknowledged the importance
of freedom of the press and has distinguished it from freedom of
104
105
speech, but it has not directly addressed Stewart’s thesis, nor has it

100
101

102
103

104
105

term “newsman,” which some might view as a reference to professional journalists, Stewart does not define the term, and he uses it interchangeably with the more generic term
“reporter.” Branzburg v. Hayes, 408 U.S. 665, 725–52 (1972) (Stewart, J., dissenting).
Id. at 707.
Id. at 681. Although the Court has not defined the scope of the right to gather news, by
acknowledging that the Speech and Press Clauses protect more than the mere expression
or dissemination of information, the Court has accepted the legitimacy of the autonomy
model, at least in some fashion.
448 U.S. 555 (1980).
Id. at 575 (“In guaranteeing freedoms such as those of speech and press, the First Amendment can be read as protecting the right of everyone to attend trials so as to give meaning
to those explicit guarantees.”).
See infra Part III.C.1, discussing the Court’s repeated references to the press’s unique role
as the public’s proxy.
The Court referenced Stewart’s speech in two of its cases, but only for more general
propositions. See Minneapolis Star & Tribune Co. v. Minn. Comm’r of Revenue, 460 U.S.
575, 585 (1983) (referencing Or of the Press generally to support the proposition that the
threat of taxes may operate as a censor to check critical comment by the press, undercut-

Jan. 2009]

CONCEPTIONS OF PRESS FREEDOM

393

declared that the Press Clause has any meaning apart from the
Speech Clause. Indeed, the phrase “Press Clause” appeared in only
106
five of the cases examined here. The only time the Court majority
used it was in McIntyre v. Ohio Elections Commission, but only as part of
107
a more general reference to both the “Speech and Press Clauses.”
The other four times, the phrase was used by concurring or dissent108
ing Justices, only one of whom, Chief Justice Burger, directly ad-

ting its role as a restraint on government); Houchins v. KQED, Inc., 438 U.S. 1, 14–15
(1978) (quoting Or of the Press to reject the assertion that the public and the media have a
First Amendment right to government information regarding jails and other public facilities). Stewart’s article is also cited favorably by the dissent in Leathers v. Medlock, 499 U.S.
439, 465 (1991) (Marshall, J., dissenting), and is referenced without discussion in Dun
and Bradstreet, Inc. v. Greenmoss Builders, Inc., 472 U.S. 749, 783 n.8 (1985) (Brennan, J.,
dissenting), and First National Bank of Boston v. Bellotti, 435 U.S. 765, 808 n.8 (1978)
(White, J., dissenting).
106

References to the Speech Clause were also rare. In Rosenberger v. University of Virginia, 515
U.S. 819, 841 (1995), the Court held that student publications and other printed material
are protected by the “Speech Clause of the First Amendment,” which, if true, would seem
to either render the Press Clause a nullity or require an interpretation in which “press”
connotes either non-expressive behavior (newsgathering) or a distinction between particular types of journalists. In City of Los Angeles v. Preferred Communications, Inc., 476 U.S.
488, 491 (1986), the Court noted that the media litigant’s “complaint alleged that [respondents] had violated the [media litigant’s rights under the] Free Speech Clause of the
First Amendment.” And in Bellotti, 435 U.S. at 800 (Burger, C.J., concurring), Chief Justice Burger referred to the Speech Clause in the context of his argument differentiating it
from the Press Clause. See infra notes 109–12 and accompanying text.

107

514 U.S. 334, 359 (1995) (“When interpreting the Free Speech and Press Clauses, we
must be guided by their original meaning, for ‘[t]he Constitution is a written instrument.’” (first alteration in original) (quoting South Carolina v. United States, 199 U.S.
437, 448 (1905))).

108

In International Society for Krishna Consciousness, Inc. v. Lee, 505 U.S. 672 (1992), Justice
Kennedy’s concurrence makes general reference to the “Speech and Press Clauses” without discussing the distinctions between them. Id. at 694, 696, 703 (Kennedy, J., concurring in judgment). In Zurcher v. Stanford Daily, 436 U.S. 547 (1978), Justice Powell, in a
concurring opinion, implied that perhaps the Press Clause has a meaning independent of
the Speech Clause but he did not elaborate. Id. at 568 (Powell, J., concurring) (“As I understand [Justice Stewart’s dissenting] opinion, it would read into the Fourth Amendment, as a new and per se exception, the rule that any search of an entity protected by the
Press Clause of the First Amendment is unreasonable so long as a subpoena could be
used as a substitute procedure.”). Justice Marshall was more explicit in his dissenting
opinion in Leathers v. Medlock, 499 U.S. 439 (1991), when he argued that a tax scheme
that treated the cable media differently than other media violated the non-discrimination
principle of the “Free Press Clause” and suggesting that the purpose of that Clause “‘was
to preserve an untrammeled press as a vital source of public information.’” Id. at 454–55
(Marshall, J., dissenting) (quoting Grosjean v. Am. Press Co., 297 U.S. 233, 250 (1936)).
Still, it is unclear whether Marshall was suggesting that there is an antidiscrimination
principle uniquely applicable to the press or whether he was merely using press language
to restate the more general First Amendment presumption against speaker-based discrimination. See Minneapolis Star & Tribune Co., 460 U.S. at 579 (striking down state laws
taxing ink and newsprint, which placed unique burdens on print media).

394

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:2

dressed the clause’s constitutional significance. In his concurring
109
opinion in First National Bank of Boston v. Bellotti, Burger surveyed
the history of the Press Clause and concluded that it was not meant to
be a source of unique protections for the institutional press but was
meant merely as an extension of the Speech Clause, guaranteeing all
people the ability to express ideas through “every sort of publication
110
Burger also
which affords a vehicle of information and opinion.”
appeared to target Stewart directly, arguing, “To conclude that the
Framers did not intend to limit the freedom of the press to one select
group is not necessarily to suggest that the Press Clause is redun111
dant.” Burger’s Bellotti concurrence was a plain articulation of the
expression model in that he emphasized the equal right of people to
communicate through media, without acknowledging any of the less
obvious ways in which expression and press independence can be
impaired by government. It was also a repudiation of the specialrights model and an example of how that model—and by extension
Justice Stewart—has been set up as the foil, despite the fact that the
media litigants have not contended that the Press Clause carves out
special protections for the institutional media or other discrete
112
groups.
The Court’s majority has not addressed these issues as squarely as
Burger did, and its approach has been haphazard. Instead of relying
on the Press Clause as the textual hook for its decisions, the Court
has used an assortment of words and phrases—“the First Amendment,” “freedom of speech and press,” “press freedom” and “freedom
of the press”—to frame the media litigants’ claims. These distinctions are not necessarily minor matters of style. They reflect (or
could be perceived as reflecting) the Court’s assumptions about the

109

110
111

112

435 U.S. at 799–800 (Burger, C.J., concurring) (“The Speech Clause standing alone may
be viewed as a protection of the liberty to express ideas and beliefs, while the Press Clause
focuses specifically on the liberty to disseminate expression broadly . . . . Yet there is no
fundamental distinction between expression and dissemination.” (footnote omitted)).
Id. at 800 (internal quotation marks omitted) (quoting Lovell v. Griffin, 303 U.S. 444, 452
(1938)).
Id. at 799. Burger added, “The liberty encompassed by the Press Clause, although complementary to and a natural extension of Speech Clause liberty, merited special mention
simply because it had been more often the object of official restraints.” Id. at 800. Although Burger did not name Stewart, his repeated references to the “institutional press”
and to protections for “a select group” suggest he was aiming his critique at the specialrights model. Id. at 799. Even more conspicuous is his use of the word “redundant,”
which is likely a reference to Stewart’s admonition that merging the Speech and Press
Clauses would create a “constitutional redundancy.” Stewart, supra note 69, at 633.
See infra Part III.B.2.

Jan. 2009]

CONCEPTIONS OF PRESS FREEDOM

395

identity of the litigants and the constitutional import of the underlying controversy.
The Court is clearly uncertain about what restrictions violate freedom of speech versus freedom of the press. It describes Miami Herald
113
Publishing Co. v. Tornillo, for example, exclusively in press terms
114
even though it is essentially a garden-variety compelled speech case.
The fact that the law in question in that case targeted newspapers was
incidental to the outcome. Nevertheless, the Court’s opinion—
strangely, written by Chief Justice Burger—never mentions the word
“speech” and instead emphasizes the importance of media independence and the ways in which the law in question “violates the guarantees
115
of a free press.” This has led some, including Justice Stewart, to hold
116
It has also left the imTornillo up as the consummate press case.
pression that perhaps a different constitutional template must be applied when the target of government restraints is a media or press defendant.
That might not be the interpretation the Court intended, but it is
a plausible one in light of the way the Court framed the case. Even if
the Court meant only to acknowledge the expressive rights of the
press and not to either differentiate them from those of other citizens
or to identify a broader zone of autonomy for the press, that does not
explain why the Court has addressed the claims of other newspaper
117
118
defendants, as well as those of other media defendants, as ones

113

114

115

116
117

118

418 U.S. 241, 243 (1974) (“The issue in this case is whether a state statute granting a political candidate a right to equal space to reply to criticism and attacks on his record by a
newspaper violates the guarantees of a free press.”).
The compelled speech doctrine stands for the principle that government may not force
someone to speak any more than it can prohibit someone from speaking. See, e.g., W. Va.
State Bd. of Educ. v. Barnette, 319 U.S. 624 (1943) (striking down law that compelled
public school students to recite the Pledge of Allegiance).
Tornillo, 418 U.S. at 243 (emphasis added). There are several similar references in the
opinion, including the Court’s ultimate declaration of its ruling: “It has yet to be demonstrated how governmental regulation of [the editorial] process can be exercised consistent with First Amendment guarantees of a free press as they have evolved to this time.” Id.
at 258 (emphasis added).
See Stewart, supra note 69, at 633.
See, e.g., Hazelwood Sch. Dist. v. Kuhlmeier, 484 U.S. 260, 262 (1988) (addressing the First
Amendment violation claims of school newspaper staff members); Seattle Times Co. v.
Rhinehart, 467 U.S. 20, 32 (1984) (addressing the media’s desire to disseminate information “obtained pursuant to a court order that both granted him access to that information and placed restraints on the way in which the information might be used”).
See, e.g., Reno v. ACLU, 521 U.S. 844 (1997) (Internet); Denver Area Educ. Telecomm.
Consortium, Inc. v. FCC, 518 U.S. 727 (1996) (cable television); Simon & Schuster, Inc. v.
N.Y. State Crime Victims Bd., 502 U.S. 105 (1991) (books); Hustler Magazine, Inc. v. Fal-

396

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:2

involving freedom of speech, not freedom of the press. Indeed, the
Court even addressed CBS v. Democratic National Committee as a speech
case though it was factually parallel to Tornillo except that the peti119
tioner was a broadcaster instead of a newspaper.
This cannot be
explained by simply distinguishing between print and broadcast media either because the Court characterizes some broadcast cases as
120
press cases as well. In a number of cases, the Court refers to freedom of speech and freedom of press in the same sentence without
121
differentiation, which could be a deliberate attempt by the Court to
remain agnostic on the relationship between the two clauses. It could
also be an expression-model fusion of the two clauses, although that
does not explain why the Court in other cases very deliberately em122
phasizes one or the other.
The Court’s media decisions do not resolve questions about the
123
scope of, and connections between, the Speech and Press Clauses.
Based purely on outcomes, the Court’s approach is most akin to the
expression model outlined by Justice Burger. But its inconsistent use
of language and its acknowledgement in Branzburg, Richmond Newspapers, and other cases that the First Amendment protects more than
just expressive acts, prevents such a clean categorization. Although it
has refused to parse the Speech and Press Clauses, the Court’s linguistic imprecision has left considerable doubt as to what the Court
regards as a violation of freedom of speech versus freedom of the
press.

119

120

121

122

123

well, 485 U.S. 46 (1988) (magazines); FCC v. Pacifica Found., 438 U.S. 726 (1978) (radio).
412 U.S. 94 (1973). Note, however, that Justice Stewart’s concurring opinion declares
that broadcasters “are surely part of the press,” and says that if the courts were to treat private media as government actors, “[f]reedom of the press would then be gone.” Id. at
133 (Stewart, J., concurring). Justice Douglas’s opinion concurring in the judgment also
frames the case as one about freedom of the press. Id. at 148–70 (Douglas, J., concurring
in judgment).
See, e.g., Cox Broad. Corp. v. Cohn, 420 U.S. 469, 497 (1975) (“[T]he protection of freedom of the press . . . bars the State of Georgia from making appellants’ broadcast the basis of civil liability.”).
See, e.g., Turner Broad. Sys., Inc. v. FCC, 512 U.S. 622 (1994); Herbert v. Lando, 441 U.S.
153 (1979); Branzburg v. Hayes, 408 U.S. 665 (1972); Rosenbloom v. Metromedia, Inc.,
403 U.S. 29 (1971).
See, e.g., Ark. Writers’ Project, Inc. v. Ragland, 481 U.S. 221, 230 (1987) (“Such official
scrutiny of the content of publications as the basis for imposing a tax is entirely incompatible with the First Amendment’s guarantee of freedom of the press.”).
The Court leaves open questions about whether the two clauses either require or permit
distinctions to be made between litigants based on their actions (e.g., newsgathering versus expression), their identity (e.g., mainstream media versus peripheral media), both, or
neither.

Jan. 2009]

CONCEPTIONS OF PRESS FREEDOM

397

2. Media Litigants
Like the Court, the media litigants have not generally affixed their
claims to a particular clause of the First Amendment, although a few
of them have quoted Stewart’s Or of the Press speech or his other state124
ments about the Press Clause.
In FCC v. League of Women Voters of
California, the media litigants argued that “the press clause was specifically included in the Constitution to ensure that the government
could not convert the communications media into a neutral market
125
place of ideas.” And in Herbert v. Lando, the litigants made an even
fuller argument, partially quoting Stewart’s dissent in Houchins v.
KQED, Inc.:
[T]he press clause of the First Amendment was no afterthought, no mere
appendage of the speech clause, but a deeply felt response to the deprivations of press liberty that the colonists had witnessed and to which they
had been subject. In short, “[t]hat the First Amendment speaks separably of freedom of speech and freedom of the press is no constitutional
accident, but an acknowledgement of the critical role played by the press
126
in American society.”

These were the only two instances in which a litigant made an explicit attempt to separate the two clauses, although in neither case
127
did the litigant build its entire argument around the Press Clause.
Indeed, there was only one instance in which a litigant represented
128
its claim as being solely about freedom of the press. In every other
case, the litigants based their claims on “the First Amendment,” “free-

124

125

126

127

128

In addition to the references that follow, Stewart’s article was quoted in three other litigant briefs, but not to support the claim that the Press Clause has a separate meaning independent of the Speech Clause.
Brief for Appellees at 33 n.23, FCC v. League of Women Voters of Cal., 468 U.S. 364
(1984) (No. 82-912) (internal quotation marks omitted) (quoting Stewart, supra note 69,
at 636).
Brief of Respondents at 55, Herbert v. Lando, 441 U.S. 153 (1979) (No. 77-1105) (alteration in original) (quoting Houchins v. KQED, Inc., 438 U.S. 1, 17 (1978) (Stewart, J.,
concurring)).
The only other reference to the Press Clause was by the media litigant in Rosenberger who
argued that its rights were protected by the “‘Speech and Press Clause[s] of the First
Amendment.’” Brief for the Petitioners at 2, Rosenberger v. Univ. of Va., 515 U.S. 819
(1995) (No. 94-329).
See Brief for Petitioners at 28, Zurcher v. Stanford Daily, 436 U.S. 547 (1978) (No. 761484). This brief does not attempt to define freedom of the press, however, or to explain
how it is separate from freedom of speech. Nevertheless, because this case involved a
First Amendment challenge to the search of a newsroom—that is, it did not involve a direct restraint of expression—the litigants seemed to be working from an autonomy
model.

398

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:2

dom of speech and press,” or some variant that combined the two
129
principles.
Even though the litigants did not limit their claims to Press Clause
arguments or even to claims about freedom of the press, they often
characterized their rights as involving press freedom, even where they
130
also claimed a violation of their speech rights.
Some litigants
seemed to perceive a benefit in having their rights recognized as
those of the press. This was especially common among the peripheral media litigants—those using handbills, flyers, newsletters, or underground publications, for example. Their rights were treated uni131
formly by the Court as only raising free speech concerns, but most
of the peripheral media litigants claimed violations of speech and
132
Still, a few litigants—both peripheral and mainstream—
press.
133
framed their arguments only in speech terms.
This could mean
that they did not see themselves as the press, or it simply could have
been a strategic decision to avoid antagonizing the Court with claims
that might be misunderstood as demands for special status. In any
case, the litigants did not follow a consistent approach by, for example, limiting their free-speech claims to contexts in which their expressive acts were targeted, or reserving their press-based claims for
contexts in which their autonomy was targeted. They were, however,
less prone than the Court to emphasizing one or the other.
129

130

131
132

133

These included: “free speech and press,” “free speech and free press,” “freedom of
speech and press,” “freedom of speech and freedom of the press,” “freedoms of speech
and publication,” and “speech and press provisions of the First Amendment.” Id.
See, e.g., Brief for Petitioners at 12, Denver Area Educ. Telecomms. Consortium, Inc. v.
FCC, 518 U.S. 727 (1996) (No. 95-124) (arguing that for cable television operators and
programmers, a restraint of their expression violated the “speech and press provisions of
the First Amendment”).
See infra Part III.C.1.
See, e.g., Brief of Petitioner at 39, McIntyre v. Ohio Elections Comm’n, 514 U.S. 334
(1995) (No. 93-986); Brief for the Appellee at 24, FEC v. Mass. Citizens for Life, Inc., 479
U.S. 238 (1986) (No. 85-701); Brief for the Plaintiff-Appellees at 64, USPS v. Council of
Greenburgh Civic Ass’ns, 453 U.S. 114 (1981) (No. 80-608); Brief of Respondents at 13,
Heffron v. Int’l Soc’y for Krishna Consciousness, Inc., 452 U.S. 640 (1981) (No. 80-795);
Brief for the Appellants at 21, Old Dominion Branch No. 496 v. Austin, 418 U.S. 264
(1974) (No. 72-1180); Brief for Petitioner at 16, Lloyd Corp. v. Tanner, 407 U.S. 551
(1972) (No. 71-492).
See, e.g., Brief of Appellee at 10, United States v. Playboy Entm’t Group, Inc., 529 U.S. 803
(2000) (No. 98-1682); Brief of Appellees at 1, Reno v. ACLU, 521 U.S. 844 (1997) (No.
96-511); Brief for Appellants at 33, Turner Broad. Sys., Inc. v. FCC, 520 U.S. 180 (1997)
(No. 95-992); Brief of Petitioners & Cross-Respondents at 12, Int’l Soc. for Krishna Consciousness, Inc. v. Lee, 505 U.S. 672 (1992) (Nos. 91-155, 91-339); Reply Brief of Petitioner at 1, Burson v. Freeman, 504 U.S. 191 (1992) (No. 90-1056); Brief of Respondents
at 20, Milkovich v. Lorain Journal Co., 497 U.S. 1 (1990) (No. 89-645); Brief for Respondent at 11, FCC v. Pacifica Found., 438 U.S. 726 (1978) (No. 77-528).

Jan. 2009]

CONCEPTIONS OF PRESS FREEDOM

399

Most importantly, the litigants’ briefs do not reflect a broad embrace of the special-rights model or a desire to separate the Speech
134
and Press Clauses. There were only a couple of exceptions, but
even in those cases the litigants did not seek to secure special rights
135
for the institutional press, though, like the Court, they highlighted
136
the press’s unique democratic role. Instead, those cases reflect the
litigants’ broader commitment to the autonomy model in which journalists and the public enjoy an equal right to express themselves, and
in which journalists—that is, all those serving a journalistic function—are protected against government incursions on their newsgathering.
This might appear to be a substantial departure from the Court’s
approach, but that is less true in terms of rationales than outcomes.
The Court’s acknowledgement in Branzburg that some pre-expressive
acts are protected, and its holding in Richmond Newspapers that the
press and public have a right to acquire information, at least in some
contexts, suggests that the Court and the litigants have not been
working from polar frameworks. By seeking qualified protections
137
against newsroom searches, inquiries into journalists’ editorial
138
139
processes, and forced disclosure of source identities, among other
things, the media litigants were simply finishing the Court’s thought
in Branzburg that the First Amendment protects more than speech.
Similarly, the litigants’ pursuit of affirmative rights of access, which
140
the Court treated with particular disdain in Pell v. Procunier, Saxbe v.
141
142
Washington Post Co., and Houchins v. KQED, Inc., is conceptually

134
135
136

137

138
139
140
141

See supra notes 125–29 and accompanying text.
See infra Part III.C.1.
The litigants in Houchins emphasized the fact that the rights they were seeking were less
for their own benefit than “for the benefit of all of us.” Brief for Respondents at 24,
Houchins v. KQED, Inc., 438 U.S. 1 (1978) (No. 76-1310) (quoting Time, Inc. v. Hill, 385
U.S. 374, 389 (1967)). And in Herbert, the litigants pointed out that the Framers “knew
how crucial a role [the press] could play in shaping government.” Brief of Respondents
at 51, Herbert v. Lando, 441 U.S. 153 (1979) (No. 77-1105); see also infra Part III.C.2.
See Zurcher v. Stanford Daily, 436 U.S. 547, 552 (1978) (addressing media-litigants’ action
seeking declaratory and injunctive relief against the police officers who searched their
newspaper).
See Herbert, 441 U.S. at 158 (rejecting protections under the First Amendment for inquiries into journalists’ editorial processes).
See Branzburg v. Hayes, 408 U.S. 665, 667 (1972) (holding that questioning reporters before a grand jury does not abridge freedom of speech).
417 U.S. 817, 835 (1974) (upholding state prison policy prohibiting media interviews with
inmates).
417 U.S. 843, 850 (1974) (upholding federal prison policy prohibiting media interviews
with inmates).

400

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:2

compatible with the Court’s argument in Richmond Newspapers that
the First Amendment safeguards not only expressive freedom, but
also some of the antecedent acts that make that freedom meaning143
ful.
B. Special Rights
This section addresses whether and to what extent the Court has
either established special rights for certain groups or media, or provided a doctrinal foundation for the recognition of such rights. More
importantly, it evaluates the media briefs to see if the litigants have
urged recognition of special press rights, and if so, on what basis.
1. U.S. Supreme Court
Although the Court’s rulings consistently eschew special rights, its
rationales and definitions are more nebulous. The Court addressed
the question of special press rights at length in Branzburg when it held
that journalists may not claim immunity against the execution of
grand jury subpoenas or any other generally applicable require144
The Court insisted that the press has neither a “liments.
145
cense . . . to violate valid criminal laws” nor “a testimonial privilege
146
that other citizens do not enjoy.” Justice Stewart, joined by Justices
Brennan and Marshall, argued in dissent that without at least qualified protection, the government could “annex the journalistic profes147
sion as an investigative arm of government.”

142
143

144

145
146
147

438 U.S. 1, 15–16 (1978) (upholding county prison policy prohibiting news media from
bringing cameras or recording equipment into jail and from interviewing inmates).
See Richmond Newspapers, Inc. v. Virginia, 448 U.S. 555, 575–76 (1980) (recognizing the
right to attend criminal trials as giving meaning to the protections of the First Amendment).
Branzburg, 408 U.S. at 682–83 (“It is clear that the First Amendment does not invalidate
every incidental burdening of the press that may result from the enforcement of civil or
criminal statutes of general applicability. Under prior cases, otherwise valid laws serving
substantial public interests may be enforced against the press as against others, despite
the possible burden that may be imposed.”).
Id. at 691.
Id. at 690.
Id. at 725 (Stewart, J., dissenting). Stewart argued that a qualified privilege would not
necessarily confer special rights on journalists as individuals, but give the press as an institution the freedom it needs to serve society’s interest “in a full and free flow of information to the public.” Id. This instrumental press function, according to Stewart, “underlies
the Constitution’s protection of a free press.” Id. at 725–26. Stewart therefore proposed
not a regime of special rights for individuals, but protections for an institution whose
“constitutional mission” is to serve the informational needs of the public. Id. at 729.

Jan. 2009]

CONCEPTIONS OF PRESS FREEDOM

401

The Court, meanwhile, was particularly troubled by the definitional dilemma that recognition of a reporter’s privilege would present. Its decision was mostly rooted in the expression model in that it
denied protection for pre-expressive activity while also describing
freedom of the press as a “‘fundamental personal right’ which ‘is not
confined to newspapers and periodicals,’” but “‘comprehends every
sort of publication which affords a vehicle of information and opin148
ion.’”
Branzburg was the first of several cases in which the Court
raised the specter of special rights and used it as a basis for rejecting
149
the media’s claims. The Court in Branzburg essentially says that because everyone can be a member of the press, the Court cannot recognize the protection being sought. But the conclusion does not follow from the premise. The Court confounds itself by intermingling
the two key models of the press. Its premise reflects the egalitarian
conception of the press and is focused on the functions being performed by those seeking recognition of the privilege. But the Court’s
conclusion reverts back to the expert conception of the press by assuming that some delineation based on identity (e.g., qualifications,
characteristics, institutional affiliations) would be necessary to apply
the privilege.
In the end, the Court never addresses the fact that a truly egalitarian conception of the press largely solves the special-rights dilemma.
The Constitution does not assign any rights to particular groups of
citizens to the exclusion of others, except to the extent that a person
claiming a right must be engaged in the behavior—or find himself in
the circumstance—for which the right was established. To invoke the
150
Second Amendment, for example, one must own or seek to own a
151
weapon. To invoke the Third Amendment, one must own or oc-

148

149

150
151

Id. at 704 (quoting Lovell v. City of Griffin, 303 U.S. 444, 450, 452 (1938)). In this sense,
the “press” is merely a channel of communication, not a set of behaviors. So, when the
Court emphasizes freedom of the press, it is merely acknowledging the fact that the expression in question was being disseminated through a particular medium. That does
not explain why the Court in other cases suggests that freedom of the press also encompasses some non-expressive activity, like gathering news and attending court proceedings.
See supra notes 137–43 and accompanying text.
See also, e.g., Cohen v. Cowles Media, 501 U.S. 663, 670 (1991) (“It is, therefore, beyond
dispute that ‘[t]he publisher of a newspaper has no special immunity from the application of general laws.’” (alteration in original) (quoting Assoc. Press v. NLRB, 301 U.S.
103, 132–33 (1937))); Herbert v. Lando, 441 U.S. 153, 165 (1979) (“The rules are applicable to the press and to other defendants alike . . . .”).
U.S. CONST. amend. II (“[T]he right of the people to keep and bear Arms, shall not be
infringed.”).
U.S. CONST. amend. III (“No Soldier shall . . . be quartered in any house . . . .”).

402

[Vol. 11:2

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW
152

cupy a residence. To invoke the Sixth Amendment, one must be
charged with a federal crime, and so on. But these kinds of qualifying criteria are inseparable from the purpose of the underlying right.
These are rights possessed by everyone, even if only some citizens will
ever have a need to assert them. On the other hand, to impose eligibility requirements that are either unrelated or tangentially related to
the purpose of the right would present a special-rights problem. Providing a First Amendment reporter’s privilege only to those who work
for traditional news organizations, who have college degrees, or who
153
work as journalists “for gain or livelihood” would arbitrarily exclude
some whose actions advance the core purposes of the right. The
problem is that the litigants have never supported the application of
154
such narrow criteria.
Not only has the Court routinely misconstrued the nature of special rights, but also it has subtly left the false
155
impression that the litigants have pursued them.
The Court addressed the issue of special rights in several other
cases. In Pell v. Procunier, the Court rejected the media litigant’s
claim of a right of access to state prisons for the purpose of interview156
ing specific inmates.
“The Constitution does not . . . require gov157
ernment to accord the press special access to information,” the Court
wrote. Justice Stewart authored the majority opinion, and while it
might appear to contradict his dissent in Branzburg, the two are reconcilable. Pell involved a claim for recognition of an affirmative right
of access—that is, a right that compelled the government to act in
158
some way to facilitate the claimants’ interests, while Branzburg and

152

153
154
155

156
157
158

U.S. CONST. amend. VI (“In all criminal prosecutions, the accused shall enjoy the right to
a speedy and public trial, by an impartial jury of the State and district wherein the crime
shall have been committed . . . .”).
This language is used in several state shield laws. See, e.g., FLA. STAT. § 90.5015(1)(a)
(2006).
See infra Part III.B.2.
In Branzburg, Zurcher, Houchins, and Cohen, among other cases, the Court set up the mainstream media litigants as the antagonists by implying that their aim was to appropriate the
First Amendment for their own purposes. See First Nat’l Bank of Boston v. Bellotti, 435
U.S. 765, 782 (1978) (“[T]he press does not have a monopoly on either the First
Amendment or the ability to enlighten.”).
417 U.S. 817, 828 (1974).
Id. at 834 (emphasis added).
The Court has not been entirely consistent with respect to affirmative rights. In Branzburg, the Court said that “news gathering is not without its First Amendment protections,”
which could imply the existence of access rights, although it need not be interpreted that
way. Branzburg v. Hayes, 408 U.S. 665, 707 (1972). More significantly, the Court recognized First and Fourteenth Amendment rights of access for the press and public to various court proceedings. See supra note 20. Certainly these conclusions are defensible, but

Jan. 2009]

CONCEPTIONS OF PRESS FREEDOM

403

most other cases were about negative rights—that is, shields against
159
government interference of some kind. The Court’s opinion in Pell
was less a repudiation of special rights than a rejection of affirmative
rights. As Stewart wrote for the Court in Pell:
It is one thing to say that a journalist is free to seek out sources of information not available to [others] . . . . It is quite another thing to suggest
that the Constitution imposes upon government the affirmative duty to
make available to journalists sources of information not available to
160
members of the public generally.

In Saxbe v. Washington Post Co., Justice Stewart again wrote for the
Court and rejected the claims of the media litigants who had challenged the constitutionality of a federal prison ban on inmate inter161
Stewart framed the case as one involving special access
views.
rights. But because the prison policy did “not place the press in any
less advantageous position than the public generally,” he found that
162
the press had no valid First Amendment claim.
Justice Powell,
joined by Justices Brennan and Marshall, concurred in part and dissented in part in both Pell and Saxbe, employing the same rationale
advanced by Stewart in his Branzburg dissent—that freeing the press
serves larger societal interests in public information. Powell wrote
that because universal access is impractical, “[t]he press is the necessary representative of the public’s interest . . . and the instrumentality
163
which effects the public’s right.” But Powell took this rationale further than Stewart, who refused to read the First Amendment as a
mandate for affirmative rights.
164
The last of the prison-access cases was Houchins v. KQED, Inc., in
which the Court rejected a broadcaster’s claim for a right of access to
a county jail where a prisoner suicide had occurred. The Court held
that “the media have no special right of access to the Alameda County
Jail different from or greater than that accorded the public gener-

159

160

161
162
163
164

it is puzzling that the Court is so dismissive of access claims in some contexts when it has
embraced them in others.
Stewart explicitly rejected recognition of affirmative rights in his Yale speech. See Stewart,
supra note 69, at 636 (“The Constitution itself is neither a Freedom of Information Act
nor an Official Secrets Act.”).
417 U.S. at 834. This was one of several cases in which the Court mischaracterized the
claims of the media litigants. The litigants did not demand to be afforded access to information unavailable to the public. Instead, they proposed a public right of access, but
emphasized the acuteness of their interest in light of their social and professional role as
conduits of public information.
417 U.S. 843, 850 (1974).
Id. at 849.
Id. at 864 (Powell, J., dissenting).
438 U.S. 1 (1978).

404

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:2

165

ally.” Indeed, neither the press nor the public has any right of access to government information, the Court held, at least in this con166
text.
There may be public policy rationales for permitting access,
but that is not the province of the judiciary. The Court wrote: “We
must not confuse what is ‘good,’ ‘desirable,’ or ‘expedient’ with what
is constitutionally commanded by the First Amendment. To do so is
167
to trivialize constitutional adjudication.”
Justice Stevens, joined by
Justices Brennan and Powell, dissented in Houchins to argue that the
case was not really about special rights; it was about a more general
public right of access. The fact that the first person to invoke this
168
right happened to be a reporter was merely coincidental. This was
essentially how the litigants framed their arguments in Houchins and
169
other access cases, but the Court implied that the litigants tried to
separate themselves from the public, not merely in terms of their capacity to broadly disseminate public information but in terms of their
entitlement to that information in the first place.
In addition to these early access cases, the Court applied its bogus
special-rights framework in several other cases that, like Branzburg,
raised questions about journalistic autonomy, as opposed to speech
or access. In each case, the Court largely applied an expressionmodel analysis and rejected the litigants’ claims. In Zurcher v. Stanford
170
Daily, the Court held that the First Amendment does not prevent
police from executing an otherwise valid search of a newsroom just
171
because its occupants are “the press.” Justice Stewart dissented, arguing that newsroom searches are self-evident violations of “freedom
172
of the press” that chill speech and undermine reporters’ confiden-

165
166

167
168

169
170
171

172

Id. at 16 (emphasis added).
Id. at 15 (“Neither the First Amendment nor the Fourteenth Amendment mandates a
right of access to government information or sources of information within the government’s control.”).
Id. at 13.
Id. at 25 (Stevens, J., dissenting) (noting that the litigant’s claim did not “rest on the
premise that the press has a greater right of access to information regarding prison conditions than do other members of the public” and therefore the litigant should not be
punished merely because members of the public “have not yet sought to vindicate their
rights”).
See supra note 160; see also infra Part III.B.2.
436 U.S. 547 (1978).
Id. at 565 (“Properly administered, the preconditions for a warrant—probable cause,
specificity with respect to the place to be searched and the things to be seized, and overall
reasonableness—should afford sufficient protection against the harms that are assertedly
threatened by warrants for searching newspaper offices.”).
Id. at 571 (Stewart, J., dissenting).

Jan. 2009]

CONCEPTIONS OF PRESS FREEDOM

405

173

tial source relationships. Although Zurcher appears to be a rejection
of special press rights and a manifestation of the expression model,
the Court actually embraced the essential argument asserted by the
litigants: “A seizure reasonable as to one type of material in one set174
ting may be unreasonable in a different setting” and where a seizure targets material “protected by the First Amendment, the requirements of the Fourth Amendment must be applied with
175
‘scrupulous exactitude.’” So, the divide between the Court and the
litigants in Zurcher was less about the principle of autonomy than
about the appropriateness of the litigants’ proposed remedy.
In light of this, one might have expected the Court to have been
more solicitous the next year in Herbert v. Lando, in which the Court
held that it does not violate the First Amendment rights of journalists
to permit libel plaintiffs to inquire into their editorial decision176
making processes when trying to establish actual malice. The plain177
tiff in that case, a public figure, argued that it would be impossible
to prove actual malice without seeking to understand what the defendants knew at the time of publication. The defendants argued
that without some kind of constitutional shield against such inquiries,
178
full and candid discussion would vanish from American newsrooms
and the press would lose much of its independence from govern179
ment.
The litigants’ autonomy argument again was misconstrued
by the Court as a selfish demand for special rights. “The rules are
180
applicable to the press and to other defendants alike,” the Court insisted, making no mention of Zurcher and its recognition of press autonomy as a constitutional principle.
The Court in Herbert did revisit its decisions in Tornillo and CBS v.
Democratic National Committee, concluding that they only prevent gov173

174
175
176
177

178
179

180

Id. at 571–73. Stewart argued that the press was not absolutely immune from searches,
but that the government should be required to first seek the information through a subpoena.
Id. at 564 (internal quotation marks omitted) (quoting Roaden v. Kentucky, 413 U.S. 496,
501 (1973)).
Id. (quoting Stanford v. Texas, 379 U.S. 476, 485 (1965)).
441 U.S. 153, 158 (1979).
Public figures suing for libel must prove that the defendant published the allegedly false
and defamatory statements with actual malice. See Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc., 418 U.S.
323, 342 (1974).
Brief of Respondents at 35, Herbert, 441 U.S. 153 (No. 77-1105).
Id. at 46 (“One question this case poses is thus whether the same public officials and public figures against whom the press—at its best—is to guard are to be permitted to compel
answers to questions at the heart of the press’s decision-making process regarding what to
print about them.”).
Herbert, 441 U.S. at 165.

406

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:2

ernment interference with media messages; they do not erect an im181
penetrable shield around the press.
Justice Brennan’s dissent objected to that idea, noting: “Through the editorial process expression
is composed; to regulate the process is therefore to regulate the ex182
pression. The autonomy of the speaker is thereby compromised.”
Brennan urged recognition of a qualified editorial privilege that
would shield defendants against this form of discovery unless the
183
plaintiff first proved the publication was both false and defamatory.
Brennan wrote that this privilege should not be conferred upon
journalists as individuals to prevent interference with their individual
184
self-expression.
Instead, it should be recognized because the de185
fendants are “representatives of the communications media” and
they have a “special and constitutionally recognized role
of . . . informing and educating the public, offering criticism, and
186
providing a forum for discussion and debate.”
The Court took a similar approach in Cohen v. Cowles Media Co.,
holding that journalists who break promises to their sources can be
sued under the doctrine of promissory estoppel without triggering
187
the First Amendment.
The Court treated this as another demand
by the litigants for special rights and immunities from generally ap188
plicable laws.
But the litigants did not base their claim on their
special identity. They simply noted that because they revealed the
181

182

183
184
185
186

187
188

Id. at 166–67. The Court leaves the impression here that its decisions only prohibit direct
restraints of expression, but the Court does not mention its statement in Branzburg that
newsgathering is protected, even though Justice White wrote the majority opinion in both
cases.
Id. at 190 (Brennan, J., dissenting). This was a perfect expression of the autonomy model
in that it acknowledged the indirect effects of government actions or subpoenas while also adding that these threats raise constitutional problems “whether [the] speaker is a
large urban newspaper or an individual pamphleteer.” Id.
Id. at 197. This would be sufficient, he argued, to protect press defendants against abuse
of the discovery process by plaintiffs.
Id. at 184 n.1 (“So grounded, an editorial privilege might not stop short of shielding all
speech.”).
Id. at 188.
Id. at 189 (internal quotation marks omitted) (quoting First Nat’l Bank of Boston v. Bellotti, 435 U.S. 765, 781 (1978)). It might appear that Brennan was recognizing special
rights, but, in fact, he was emphasizing the special role played by the press while also recognizing that it is a role that anyone can play. See, e.g., infra note 197.
501 U.S. 663, 672 (1991).
Id. at 670 (“It is, therefore, beyond dispute that ‘[t]he publisher of a newspaper has no
special immunity from the application of general laws. He has no special privilege to invade
the rights and liberties of others.’ Accordingly, enforcement of such general laws against
the press is not subject to stricter scrutiny than would be applied to enforcement against
other persons or organizations.” (emphasis added) (alteration in original) (citation omitted) (quoting Associated Press v. NLRB, 301 U.S. 103, 132–33 (1937))).

Jan. 2009]

CONCEPTIONS OF PRESS FREEDOM

407

name of their source in the context of a news story about a matter of
significant public interest, their First Amendment interests ought to
189
be weighed against the plaintiff’s interests. Justice Souter and three
other Justices agreed with the litigants, arguing that “‘[t]here is nothing talismanic about neutral laws of general applicability,’” and that
190
such laws can be as suppressive as ones that target content directly.
Justice Blackmun’s dissenting opinion mirrored the arguments of the
litigants by suggesting that the case was governed by Smith v. Daily
191
Mail Publishing Co., which held that truthful speech on matters of
public interest can only be restricted to serve “a state interest of the
192
highest order.”
The Court, however, ignored the expression issue
altogether and represented the case as one about media exclusivity.
Although the Court has generally opposed recognition of special
rights for the press, it muddled its position on this issue in a series of
libel cases in the 1970s and 1980s. The Court used language in these
cases suggesting that the rights of media defendants are different
than those of other defendants. In Rosenbloom v. Metromedia, Inc., the
Court wrote, “We expressly leave open the question of what constitutional standard of proof, if any, controls the enforcement of state libel laws for defamatory falsehoods published or broadcast by news me193
194
dia.”
Three years later in Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc., the Court’s
opinion repeatedly emphasized the interests of “the press and the
195
broadcast media.” The Court did the same in Time, Inc. v. Firestone,
in which it wrote that “[b]y requiring a showing of fault the Court in
Gertz sought to shield the press and broadcast media from a rule of strict
196
liability.”
In Philadelphia Newspapers, Inc. v. Hepps, the Court held
“that the common-law presumption that defamatory speech is false

189
190

191
192

193
194
195
196

Brief of Respondent at 29, Cohen, 501 U.S. 663 (No. 90-634).
Cohen, 501 U.S. at 677 (Souter, J., dissenting) (alteration in original) (internal quotation
marks omitted) (quoting Employment Div., Dep’t of Human Res. of Or. v. Smith, 494
U.S. 872, 901 (1990) (O’Connor, J., concurring)).
443 U.S. 97 (1979).
Id. at 103. Blackmun also insisted that Cohen was about expression, not special rights, and
that “[n]ecessarily, the First Amendment protection afforded respondents would be
equally available to nonmedia defendants.” Cohen, 501 U.S. at 673 (Blackmun, J., dissenting).
403 U.S. 29, 44 n.12 (1971) (emphasis added).
418 U.S. 323 (1974).
Id. at 337.
424 U.S. 448, 465 (1976) (emphasis added). See also Cox Broad. v. Cohn, 420 U.S. 469,
499 (1975) (Powell, J., concurring) (explaining that in Gertz the Court “held that the First
Amendment prohibits the States from imposing strict liability for media publication of allegedly false statements that are claimed to defame a private individual” (emphasis added)).

408

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:2

cannot stand when a plaintiff seeks damages against a media defendant
197
for speech of public concern.”
Four years later, in Milkovich v.
Lorain Journal Co., the Court wrote, “we think Hepps stands for the
proposition that a statement on matters of public concern must be
provable as false before there can be liability under state defamation
198
law, at least in situations . . . where a media defendant is involved.”
The next year, however, the Court described a libel case involving The
New Yorker as a free-speech case, with no reference to the press or any
199
special protections that might inhere in such a characterization.
Whether or not the Court intended to, or in fact did, confer spe200
cial rights on the press, it has never disavowed any of the media201
specific language from its libel decisions.
That is certainly something the Court needs to revisit. But much more consequential is the
fact that the Court has not only misconceived the nature of special
rights, it has repeatedly mischaracterized the claims of the media litigants as demands for special rights. This has very clearly affected the
outcomes of these cases, and it is not impossible to imagine that it has
also shaped public assessments of the press and the legitimacy of
their legal claims.

197

198
199

200

201

475 U.S. 767, 777 (1986) (emphasis added). Note that Justice Brennan wrote separately
in Hepps to emphasize his view that the libel principles established by the Court are equally applicable to media and non-media defendants. Id. at 779–80 (Brennan, J., concurring).
497 U.S. 1, 19–20 (1990) (emphasis added).
See Masson v. New Yorker Magazine, Inc., 501 U.S. 496, 523 (1991) (“Here, we reject any
suggestion that the incremental harm doctrine is compelled as a matter of First Amendment protection for speech.” (emphasis added)).
The Court has not found a constitutional defect in legislative schemes that provide subsidies or other benefits to the media. See, e.g., L.A. Police Dep’t v. United Reporting Publ’g
Corp., 528 U.S. 32 (1999) (finding constitutional a state records statute that gave news
organizations and others access but did not permit access for commercial requesters);
Leathers v. Medlock, 499 U.S. 439 (1991) (holding that it does not violate the First
Amendment for the government to apply its generally applicable sales tax requirements
to cable television services alone while exempting the print media).
C. Edwin Baker points out that, in Dun & Bradstreet, Inc. v. Greenmoss Builders, Inc., 472
U.S. 749, 758–59 (1985), a majority of the Justices (four dissenting Justices and one concurring Justice) rejected the application of different libel criteria to a non-media defendant. Baker, supra note 28, at 957. That is true but it does not settle the issue, particularly in light of the reference just noted from Milkovich, 497 U.S. at 19–20, which was
written four years after Dun & Bradstreet in a seven-member majority opinion. Individual
Justices have repudiated the special-rights rhetoric from the libel cases, but the Court majority has never addressed it.

Jan. 2009]

CONCEPTIONS OF PRESS FREEDOM

409

2. Media Litigants
The media litigant briefs largely reflect an autonomy-model of the
First Amendment, which is not built around the special status or identity of the claimants but around the functions they perform. It is also
a model that recognizes the threats posed to journalistic autonomy by
regulations targeting some non-expressive activity. There were some
instances in which the litigants emphasized their press credentials or
highlighted the important social role of the press. But that is not to
say that they sought to position themselves atop some constitutional
pecking order.
It is possible that some of the litigants thought they might derive
some benefit from being viewed as “the press” and that it would be a
factor in the Court’s constitutional calculus. Because the Court in
some cases deliberately emphasized freedom of the press rather than
202
freedom of speech, it is understandable that some litigants might
have hoped for some special allowance, even though it was not something they explicitly sought. Indeed, the media litigants often made
it clear that they were not seeking recognition of a separate sphere of
203
protections for the institutional media and that the rights they were
pursuing were not for their own benefit but for the benefit of the
204
public.
The closest the litigants came to making special-rights claims was
205
in the three prison-access cases. The media litigants in these cases
occasionally employed some of the rhetoric associated with an expert
conception of the press. In Pell v. Procunier, for example, they argued
that “excluding the press wrongly discriminates against them and the
constitutional interest they represent. Indeed, the First Amendment
actually grants them a preferred status, and discriminations which heavily burden First Amendment values are especially reprehensi206
ble . . . .” The litigants in Saxbe mirrored some of these arguments

202
203

204
205
206

See, e.g., Ark. Writers’ Project, Inc. v. Ragland, 481 U.S. 221 (1987); Cox Broad. Corp. v.
Cohn, 420 U.S. 469 (1975); Miami Herald Publ’g Co. v. Tornillo, 418 U.S. 241 (1974).
See, e.g., Brief for the Appellee at 69, FEC v. Mass. Citizens for Life, Inc., 479 U.S. 238
(1986) (No. 85-701) (“The liberty of the press secured by the First Amendment is not the
special province of the traditional ‘institutional press,’ but is a fundamental right which
comprehends every sort of publication.”).
See infra note 260.
Houchins v. KQED, Inc., 438 U.S. 1 (1978); Saxbe v. Wash. Post Co., 417 U.S. 843 (1974);
Pell v. Procunier, 417 U.S. 817 (1974).
Brief of Appellants at 11–12, Pell, 417 U.S. 817 (No. 918). This might be misleading in
the sense that the litigants might simply have been suggesting that press freedom is af-

410

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:2

by highlighting the “unique constitutional status of those who inform
207
the public” and the “unique expertise” the press has in “determining what matters are newsworthy and what interviews are needed in
208
order to inform the public.” Because of this expertise, the litigants
in Houchins v. KQED, Inc. contended, some differential access can be
afforded the press without upsetting the Constitution: “Freedom ‘of
the press’ need not be defined in all circumstances by the rights of
209
the public at large.” The litigants in each of these cases later turned
to the familiar arguments, endorsed by some of the Justices, that
210
press access—even “somewhat different” access —is required not to
serve the individual interests of journalists, but to facilitate their ability to deliver newsworthy information to the public.
This is an important principle underlying the litigants’ claims in
access cases, where their arguments often seemed less about constitutional hierarchies than about simple efficiencies. Specifically, they
wanted the Court to recognize that with finite space and opportunities for access, giving priority access to a journalist over a nonjournalist would yield greater social benefits. Even though their interests and their intellectual capacities might be identical, the journalist is more likely seeking access for the purpose of communicating
to the public and is likely to have access to more robust channels of
communication. So the litigants would have likely acknowledged,
and in some cases did acknowledge, that anyone can be a journalist,
but that is different from saying everyone is a journalist. And when a
government official is faced with access requests from otherwise identically situated claimants, there are sound policy reasons for giving
preference to the journalist. The litigants perhaps crossed the line,
however, in suggesting that this preference is constitutionally mandated, and that differential access is permissible because of journalists’ unique expertise.
Still, these indefinite references, which are limited to a couple of
211
early cases in the somewhat anomalous access-to-places context,

207
208
209
210
211

forded preferential (that is, explicit constitutional) recognition, not that individual
claimants are preferred over others serving similar ends.
Brief for Respondents at 28 n.8, Saxbe, 417 U.S. 843 (No. 73-1265).
Id. at 67.
Brief for Respondents at 43, Houchins, 438 U.S. 1 (No. 76-1310).
Id. at 42.
These cases are unlike most in that they are complicated by the commingling of policy
and constitutional arguments and by the conjunction of special-rights and affirmativerights issues.

Jan. 2009]

411

CONCEPTIONS OF PRESS FREEDOM
212

provide sparse evidence of a campaign for special rights.
The litigants were much more magnanimous in other cases, in which they
made no distinctions between particular types of journalists or between journalists and the press. In Richmond Newspapers, for example,
the litigant urged the Court “to recognize a First Amendment right of
213
members of the public to attend criminal trials,” which is a phrasing
214
repeated in other access cases not involving prisons.
The same was true in cases involving non-expressive activity, where
the litigants sought rights that were unique to the press, but with the
press defined in egalitarian terms. In Herbert, they urged the Court to
provide First Amendment protection against inquiries into editorial
decision-making, but they did not demand that it be confined to
215
mainstream media or to journalists of a particular order. Likewise,
in Zurcher the litigants did not rest their claim on the right of the
press to immunity from government searches, but proposed a
broader right that would provide protections whenever a search “af216
fects freedom of speech or press.”
Herbert and Zurcher are therefore
quintessential autonomy-model cases in that the litigants emphasized
a neutral principle that transcends identity. It might appear that the
media litigants in Cohen v. Cowles Media Co. sought special protections
by arguing that the government should not be able to enforce a generally applicable law against the press where it would prevent them
from communicating newsworthy information to the public about an
217
upcoming election.
But the thrust of their argument was that the
government should not be permitted to interfere with anyone’s ability
212

213
214

215
216
217

See, e.g., Houchins, 438 U.S. 1. The litigants did not seek preferential access; they simply
argued that the government could not use its desire for neutrality as a basis for denying
access altogether. In other words, the government could not simply shut down access altogether. Through this argument, the litigants also sought judicial recognition of affirmative rights, which the Court has recognized in other contexts. See supra note 20.
Brief of Appellants at 27, Richmond Newspapers, Inc. v. Virginia, 448 U.S. 555 (1980)
(No. 79-243) (emphasis added).
See, e.g., Supplemental Brief of Petitioners, El Vocero de Puerto Rico v. Puerto Rico, 508
U.S. 147 (1993) (No. 92-949); Brief of Petitioner on the Merits, Press-Enter. Co. v. Superior Court, 478 U.S. 1 (1985) (No. 84-1560); Brief for Petitioner on the Merits, PressEnter. Co. v. Superior Court, 464 U.S. 501 (1984) (No. 82-556); Reply Brief of Appellant,
Globe Newspaper Co. v. Superior Court, 457 U.S. 596 (1982) (No. 81-611); Brief of Appellants, Chandler v. Florida, 449 U.S. 560 (1981) (No. 79-1260); Brief of Appellants,
Richmond Newspapers, 448 U.S. 555 (No. 79-243); Brief of Petitioner, Gannett Co. v. DePasquale, 443 U.S. 368 (1979) (No. 77-1301); Brief for Respondent, Nixon v. Warner
Commc’ns, Inc., 435 U.S. 589 (1978) (No. 76-944).
Brief for Respondents, Herbert v. Lando, 441 U.S. 153 (1979) (No. 77-1105).
Brief for Respondents at 13, Zurcher v. Stanford Daily, 436 U.S. 547 (1977) (Nos. 761484, 76-1600) (emphasis added).
Brief of Respondent, Cohen v. Cowles Media Co., 501 U.S. 663 (1991) (No. 90-634).

412

[Vol. 11:2

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW
218

to disseminate truthful information of public interest, and that First
Amendment interests cannot be ignored merely because the law be219
ing enforced is generally applicable.
There were some hints of special-rights rhetoric by media litigants
in the libel cases, but these were probably attempts by the litigants to
mirror the Court’s linguistic patterns. In Firestone, the litigant described the holding from Gertz as one preventing liability without
220
fault in libel actions against “a member of the ‘press.’” The litigant
also argued that the Court had “long emphasized” that the role of the
press in informing the public requires “maximum freedom and special
221
protection.”
And in Masson, the litigant referenced the extent to
which libel plaintiffs could recover damages from “the press” but did
222
not expand on this. It is important to emphasize, however, that in
all other libel cases, including Hepps, the litigants broke from the
223
Court and framed their claims purely as matters of free speech.
Despite these occasional references, and despite the common al224
lusions to the unique role and function of the press, the media liti225
The evidence
gants did not demand recognition of special rights.
gathered from the briefs thus does not support the more general accusation of media exceptionalism, much less an attempt to exalt the
226
rights of particular segments of the press. Whether or not these descriptions accurately characterize the out-of-court statements of journalists and their advocates, they are not reflected in the briefs filed
with the Court.

218
219

220
221
222
223
224
225

226

Id. at 29.
Id. at 34–36. The litigants note that laws governing libel, privacy, and intentional infliction of emotional distress are all generally applicable, yet the Court has subjected their
application to some First Amendment limitations.
Brief for Petitioner at 16, Time, Inc. v. Firestone, 424 U.S. 448 (1975) (No. 74-944) (quoting Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc., 418 U.S. 323, 347–48 (1974)).
Id. at 26 (emphasis added).
Brief for Respondents at 23–24, Masson v. New Yorker Magazine, Inc., 501 U.S. 496
(1990) (No. 89-1799).
See, e.g., Brief for Appellants at 25, Phila. Newspapers, Inc. v. Hepps, 475 U.S. 767 (1985)
(No. 84-1491).
See infra Part III.C.2.
Indeed, even in cases in which the Court emphasized press autonomy or freedom of the
press, the litigants often used more neutral language and relied on more traditional arguments.
This is not to say that the litigants made no distinction between the press and the public.
They did seek some rights that would be available only to the press. But because their
claims were coupled with an egalitarian conception of the press, the litigants’ approach
did not exclude members of the public who might seek to serve the same journalistic
purposes.

Jan. 2009]

CONCEPTIONS OF PRESS FREEDOM

413

C. The Role and Identity of the Press
This section addresses the ways in which the parties defined “journalists” and “the press” and how they distinguished them from other
people and institutions. Unlike the earlier sections, which looked at
how the parties characterized the underlying claims, this section looks
at how they framed the identity and journalistic aims of the claimants.
1. U.S. Supreme Court
The Supreme Court has not explicitly defined either “journalist”
or “the press.” Of course, it deliberately skirted the issue in Branzburg
227
after refusing to recognize a reporter’s privilege. But even in its libel rulings, where the Court implied that the press might possess
228
unique constitutional protections, it acted as if the meaning of “the
press” was self-evident.
The Court’s conceptions of “journalist” and “the press” can potentially be discerned by noting the types of people and institutions to
which the Court has applied those terms. Unfortunately, the Court’s
approach has been wildly inconsistent. Despite its statement in Branzburg that “liberty of the press is the right of the lonely pamphleteer
who uses carbon paper or a mimeograph just as much as of the large
229
metropolitan publisher,” the Court’s other statements and characterizations are far less populist. The Court has consistently described
traditional, mainstream media organizations as the press, but it has
not done the same for the peripheral media. In all cases involving
mainstream magazines and daily newspapers, the Court operated
from the assumption that those organizations are part of the press
and that their claims involved either “freedom of the press” or
“speech and press.” The same was true in cases involving the main230
231
stream broadcasters and cable programmers and operators.
227
228
229
230

231

Branzburg v. Hayes, 408 U.S. 665, 704 (1972).
See supra notes 193–99 and accompanying text.
Branzburg, 408 U.S. at 704.
See, e.g., FCC v. League of Women Voters of Cal., 468 U.S. 364, 382 (1984) (“[T]he press,
of which the broadcasting industry is indisputably a part, carries out a historic, dual responsibility in our society . . . .” (citation omitted)); see also Cox Broad. Corp. v. Cohn, 420
U.S. 469, 497 (1975) (“[T]he protection of freedom of the press . . . bars the State of
Georgia from making appellants’ broadcast the basis of civil liability.”).
See, e.g., Turner Broad. Sys., Inc. v. FCC, 512 U.S. 622, 636 (1994) (“There can be no disagreement on an initial premise: Cable programmers and cable operators . . . are entitled to the protection of the speech and press provisions of the First Amendment.” (emphasis added)); see also Denver Area Educ. Telecomms. Consortium, Inc. v. FCC, 518 U.S.
727, 815 (1996) (“[C]able operators engage in speech by providing news, information,

414

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:2

Despite its famous platitude about the virtuous “lonely pamphle232
teer,” the Court has not been willing to endow communicators using less traditional media with the label “the press,” nor has it characterized their rights as involving “freedom of the press.” The Court
233
has analyzed these as speech cases, despite some occasional references by dissenting or concurring Justices to “the press” or “freedom
234
of the press.” The different characterizations of mainstream versus
peripheral media defendants suggests that the Court is employing—
though certainly not carefully articulating—a more corporate or expert conception of the press than is implied by its egalitarian statements in Branzburg. In each of these cases, the media litigant’s rights
235
were upheld.
At the very least, this creates some doctrinal confusion, even though the disparities are at the definitional level rather
than the decisional level, and are therefore less confounding in terms
of outcomes.
The discrepancies between mainstream and peripheral media
cases might make sense if the Court had simply been seeking to draw

232
233

234

235

and entertainment to their subscribers and . . . they are part of the press.” (internal quotation marks omitted)); Leathers v. Medlock, 499 U.S. 439, 444 (1991) (“Cable television
provides to its subscribers news, information, and entertainment. It is engaged in
‘speech’ under the First Amendment, and is, in much of its operation, part of the
‘press.’”). In three other cable cases, however, the Court recognized the First Amendment rights of cable operators, but focused solely on their expressive or speech rights
without specifically mentioning “the press.” See United States v. Playboy Entm’t Group,
Inc., 529 U.S. 803 (2000); Turner Broad. Sys., Inc. v. FCC, 520 U.S. 180 (1997); City of
L.A. v. Preferred Commc’ns, Inc., 476 U.S. 488 (1986).
Branzburg, 408 U.S. at 704.
See, e.g., McIntyre v. Ohio Elections Comm’n, 514 U.S. 334 (1995) (involving restrictions
on dissemination of anonymous campaign literature); Hazelwood Sch. Dist. v. Kuhlmeier,
484 U.S. 260 (1988) (addressing censorship of stories about divorce and teen pregnancy
in high school newspaper); Heffron v. Int’l Soc. for Krishna Consciousness, Inc., 452 U.S.
640 (1981) (entailing the distribution of sectarian literature at the Minnesota State Fair);
Old Dominion Branch No. 496 v. Austin, 418 U.S. 264 (1974) (involving a libel action
against a union newsletter for referring to claimants as “scabs”); Papish v. Bd. of Curators
of the Univ. of Mo., 410 U.S. 667 (1973) (pertaining to restrictions on an underground
college publication criticizing the police); Lloyd Corp. v. Tanner, 407 U.S. 551 (1972)
(addressing the restraint of handbills urging people to attend anti-war rally); Org. for a
Better Austin v. Keefe, 402 U.S. 415 (1971) (involving the distribution of leaflets accusing
real estate broker of fraud and discrimination). It should be noted that there was nothing about the content of the messages being disseminated in these peripheral media that
distinguished these cases from others. Each case involved what was arguably core speech.
See, e.g., McIntyre, 514 U.S. at 359 (Thomas, J., concurring); Hazelwood, 484 U.S. at 284
(Brennan, J., dissenting); Old Dominion Branch, 418 U.S. at 288 n.2 (Douglas, J., concurring); Lloyd Corp., 407 U.S. at 573 (Marshall, J., dissenting).
One exception, not mentioned above, was Burson v. Freeman, 504 U.S. 191 (1992), in
which the Court upheld a law limiting the distribution of literature near a polling place
on the day of an election.

Jan. 2009]

CONCEPTIONS OF PRESS FREEDOM

415

a line between dissemination (speech, distribution) and newsgather236
ing (access, autonomy).
In several cases involving the dissemination of content in mainstream media, the Court did address the First
237
Amendment claims as involving free speech, not free press, and all
of the peripheral media cases involved expression issues. But the
Court does not follow a consistent pattern, and goes out of its way in
some expression cases to identify a litigant as “the press” or to charac238
terize its claim as one involving freedom of the press.
What is it, then, that distinguishes the press? The Court is unclear. It regularly highlights the unique social role of the press—how
it monitors the abuses of government, keeps the public informed,
provides a vehicle for the exchange of ideas and enables the public’s
self-governing tasks, which subtly suggests a certain regularity of
communication and perhaps a kind of expertise that connotes an expert conception of the press. The Court also implies that an organization’s or individual’s status as a “media defendant” is relevant in de239
termining the scope of its constitutional rights, and that only
certain communicators or media organizations are capable of making
claims involving freedom of the press. Yet its more explicit statements affirm the idea that the rights of the press extend no farther
240
than those of the public and that the lonely pamphleteer is as much
“the press” as is a large daily newspaper.
The Court has been equally imprecise in its use of the terms “journalist,” “reporter,” and “newsman,” but it has been more consistent in

236
237

238

239
240

All of the peripheral-media cases were, after all, about expression issues, not access or
autonomy.
See, e.g., Reno v. ACLU, 521 U.S. 844 (1997) (involving the restriction of indecent content
on the Internet); Hustler Magazine, Inc. v. Falwell, 485 U.S. 46 (1988) (regarding a civil
suit for intentional infliction of emotional distress based on a parody advertisement published in a magazine); FCC v. Pacifica Found., 438 U.S. 726 (1978) (pertaining to a restriction on indecent content broadcast by a public radio station).
See, e.g., Cohen v. Cowles Media Co., 501 U.S. 663, 664 (1991) (stating that the First
Amendment does not immunize the press from a promissory estoppel cause of action
based on a breach of promise); Phila. Newspapers, Inc. v. Hepps, 475 U.S. 767, 768
(1986) (finding that the burden of proving the falsity of allegedly defamatory speech
cannot be placed on the press); Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc., 418 U.S. 323, 325 (1974)
(giving protection to the press from liability in defamation cases when a public issue is
discussed, absent proof of knowledge of falsity or reckless disregard of the truth); Miami
Herald Publ’g Co. v. Tornillo, 418 U.S. 241, 258 (1974) (holding that a state statute allowing for “right of reply” in newspapers violated freedom of the press); see also supra notes
230–31.
See supra Part III.B.1.
See, e.g., Branzburg v. Hayes, 408 U.S. 665, 684 (1972) (“It has generally been held that
the First Amendment does not guarantee the press a constitutional right of special access
to information not available to the public generally.”).

416

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:2

241

application. The Court uses these terms in a matter-of-fact way, apparently assuming that whatever meaning it ascribes to them is shared
by their audience. These terms are not used in every case involving
the press or media. Their application is narrower. Not every employee of a media organization is described as a journalist, for example. The Court generally characterizes people as journalists or reporters only when they publish or broadcast information of public
242
243
significance or when they seek and gather such information, and
even then only if they work in mainstream media.
Finally, the Court suggests that a journalist is someone who serves
as a watchdog and is an agent of the public. The Court says journalists and the news media serve as the “‘eyes and ears’ of the public,
[and] can be a powerful and constructive force, contributing to re244
medial action in the conduct of public business.”
Because “[n]o
individual can obtain for himself the information needed for the in245
telligent discharge of his political responsibilities,” journalists and
the news media play a “special and constitutionally recognized
246
role . . . in informing and educating the public.” This is the type of
language the Court routinely uses, and it suggests a traditional definition of journalists—one that mirrors the widely recognized Wood247
ward-and-Bernstein archetype.
Yet in other cases, the Court has
said that the press “does not have a monopoly on either the First

241

242
243

244
245
246
247

During the mid-1980s the Court was more likely to use the term “media” as opposed to
“the press” in referring to the litigants. This was probably just an attempt to acknowledge
the parallels between print media, on one hand, and broadcast, cable, and Internet media on the other. Similarly, in referring to reporters, the Court used the archaic term
“newsman” in Branzburg. But in subsequent decisions, it used “journalist” and occasionally “reporter.” In no case was the meanings of these terms specifically examined, however.
See Masson v. New Yorker Magazine, Inc., 501 U.S. 496, 499 (1991) (“The First Amendment protects . . . journalists who write about public figures . . . .” (emphasis added)).
See, e.g., Branzburg, 408 U.S. at 691 (noting that by rejecting the reporter’s privilege, the
Court was not seeking to restrain the “quality of information reporters may seek to acquire,
nor . . . threaten the vast bulk of confidential relationships between reporters and their
sources” (emphases added)).
Houchins v. KQED, Inc., 438 U.S. 1, 8 (1978).
Saxbe v. Wash. Post Co., 417 U.S. 843, 863 (1974) (Powell, J., dissenting).
First Nat’l Bank of Boston v. Bellotti, 435 U.S. 765, 781 (1978).
The Court’s characterizations of the press need not be interpreted as embracing an expert conception, but because the Court uses this language in cases involving mainstream
media, whose claims they characterize as being about freedom of the press, and because
the Court generally does not use this language in cases involving peripheral-media litigants whose cases are presented as ones involving freedom of speech, the Court creates
unnecessary confusion.

Jan. 2009]

CONCEPTIONS OF PRESS FREEDOM
248

417

Amendment or the ability to enlighten,” and that “[t]he informative function asserted by representatives of the organized press . . . is
also performed by lecturers, political pollsters, novelists, academic researchers, and dramatists. Almost any author may quite accurately
assert that he is contributing to the flow of information to the pub249
lic . . . .”
The Court implies that journalists are no different than
other communicators, at least in their expressive or informative functions. This begs the question whether they are different from others
in their newsgathering or investigative functions. The Court has suggested that they are, but at the same time has refused to provide them
with any protections—other than access to the courts, which is a right
that they share with the public—that are uniquely tied to that task.
There are several problems with the Court’s conceptions of journalists and the press. The Court emphasizes the unique role played
by the press in serving as a check on the exercise of power. Yet the
Court on many occasions has defined media organizations as the
press when they do not necessarily serve that function.
Cable television is the clearest example. Cable television system
operators, though exercising some editorial discretion in selecting
the menu of channels they offer to subscribers, do not serve a checking function, at least not directly. They provide a vehicle through
which this information reaches the public, but they usually produce
none of their own content. Perhaps these functions warrant First
Amendment protection, but to the extent that they serve a checking
function, their role is more indirect than traditional news organizations, or even intrepid bloggers or pamphleteers. The Court declares
that certain media are the press and that they are protected as such,
but if the press is defined as any organization that communicates information, that hardly distinguishes it from other institutions.
Using that criterion, it also makes little sense to characterize publishers of pamphlets, newsletters, and student newspapers as only
speakers and not also the press. In short, the Court needs to make
clear what rights the press possesses qua press. If none, then the
Court should abandon its exhaustive chronicling of the press’s storied role as the nation’s bulwark of liberty, or at least make clear that
those are functions that any motivated citizen can perform.

248
249

Bellotti, 435 U.S. at 782.
Branzburg v. Hayes, 408 U.S. 408, 705 (1972).

418

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:2

2. Media Litigants
Like the Court, no media litigant has ever proposed a specific
definition of “the press.” Nevertheless, many litigants have deliberately presented themselves to the Court as the press, perhaps hoping
or assuming this would enhance their claims to constitutional protection. In Herbert v. Lando, the media litigants insisted that although
CBS and the “60 Minutes” staff were broadcasters, they were also the
press, a point the media litigants believed had not been and could
250
251
not be disputed.
Other cases reflect this tendency as well.
The
Court was inconsistent in its characterizations of the electronic media
litigants, but the litigants themselves made more predictable efforts
252
to position themselves as the press, although this was not always the
253
case.
The peripheral media litigants were particularly determined to
convince the Court of their press status. Although the Court uniformly characterized these litigants’ claims as only involving speech,
250
251

252

253

Brief of Respondents at 26 n.1, Herbert v. Lando, 441 U.S. 153 (1979) (No. 77-1105).
See, e.g., Brief for Appellant at 21–22, Ark. Writers’ Project, Inc. v. Ragland, 481 U.S. 221
(1987) (No. 85-1370) (arguing that newspapers and magazines are both instruments of
the press); Brief for Petitioner at 32, Branzburg, 408 U.S. 665 (No. 70-85) (arguing that
“[p]etitioner is a member of the press” by virtue of being an investigative reporter for a
newspaper). These could simply have been attempts by the media litigants to distinguish
themselves from other businesses and institutions by emphasizing the fact that they engage, as part of their operations, in expressive activity, and in doing so, are covered by the
First Amendment. These need not be interpreted, in other words, as attempts by the litigants to claim broader immunities.
See, e.g., Brief for Appellants at 21, Turner Broad. Sys., Inc. v. FCC, 512 U.S. 622 (1994)
(No. 93-44) (“Sections 4 and 5 deliberately interfere with . . . the editorial functions of
members of the press . . . .”); Brief for Respondent at 29, City of L.A. v. Preferred
Commc’ns, Inc., 476 U.S. 488 (1986) (No. 85-390) (“City’s desire to manage a medium of
the press is improper.”); Brief for Appellees at 38, FCC v. League of Women Voters of Cal.,
468 U.S. 364 (1984) (No. 82-912) (“There can be no doubt that broadcasting falls within
the First Amendment’s protection against governmental abridgement of freedom of
speech and the press.”); Brief for Respondent at 52, FCC v. Midwest Video Corp., 440
U.S. 689 (1979) (Nos. 77-1575, 77-1648, 77-1662) (“[C]able systems should be accorded
the same First Amendment rights as newspapers . . . .”).
Several electronic media litigants focused on their speech rights and did not seek to
characterize themselves as the press. See Brief of Appellee at 21, United States v. Playboy
Entm’t Group, Inc., 529 U.S. 803 (2000) (No. 98-1682) (alleging that limited television
broadcasting privileges for sexually explicit programs is an unconstitutional restraint of
free speech); Brief of Appellees, Reno v. ACLU, 521 U.S. 844 (1997) (No. 96-511) (discussing indecency statutes as an unconstitutional abridgement of free speech in the context of the Internet); Brief for Appellants at 3–4, Turner Broad. Sys., Inc. v. FCC, 520 U.S.
180 (1997) (No. 95-992) (maintaining that mandatory carriage requirements for broadcast television are regulations that burden free speech); Brief for Respondent at 34, FCC
v. Pacifica Found., 438 U.S. 726 (1978) (No. 77-528) (arguing that censoring airwaves restricts freedom of expression).

Jan. 2009]

CONCEPTIONS OF PRESS FREEDOM

419

the litigants often sought to persuade the Court that they were no different, in function if not form, than the mainstream press and that
their rights under the First Amendment should parallel those of traditional newspapers, magazines, and broadcast outlets. In FEC v.
Massachusetts Citizens for Life, for example, the media litigant argued
that a pro-life newsletter should be protected as a matter of “[t]he
liberty of the press” to the same extent as “the traditional institutional
254
press.”
It argued that the restriction in question “would silence a
publication more akin to the newspapers circulated at the time the
First Amendment was written than the publications now printed by
255
media conglomerates.” In USPS v. Council of Greenburgh Civic Ass’ns,
the media litigant argued that pamphlets and leaflets “fall within the
256
purview of the free press protections,” and most other peripheral
257
media litigants made similar arguments.
The characteristics that media litigants identified as defining the
press and its social role paralleled those highlighted by the Court.
258
The litigants portrayed themselves as exercising editorial control,
communicating information of public significance relevant to the
259
“bar[ing] the secrets of governpublic’s self-governing tasks,
254
255
256
257

258
259

Brief for Appellee at 69, FEC v. Mass. Citizens for Life, Inc., 479 U.S. 238 (1986) (No 85701) (internal quotation marks omitted).
Id. at 70–71.
Brief for Plaintiffs-Appellees at 62, USPS v. Council of Greenburgh Civic Ass’ns, 453 U.S.
114 (1981) (No. 80-608).
See, e.g., Brief of Petitioner at 40, McIntyre v. Ohio Elections Comm’n, 514 U.S. 334
(1995) (No. 93-986) (describing the case as one involving speech and press, and describing political pamphlets and leaflets as “‘the poor man’s printing press’” (quoting Harry
Kalven, Jr., The Concept of the Public Forum: Cox v. Louisiana, 1965 SUP. CT. REV. 1, 30));
Brief of Respondents at 4, Hazelwood Sch. Dist. v. Kuhlmeier, 484 U.S. 260 (1988) (No.
86-836) (arguing that student newspapers are the press); Brief of Respondents at 13–14,
Heffron v. Int’l Soc. for Krishna Consciousness, Inc., 452 U.S. 640 (1981) (No. 80-795)
(describing a religious pamphleteering case as one involving “freedoms of speech, press,
religious exercise, association, and assembly”); Brief for Respondents at 15, Lloyd Corp. v.
Tanner, 407 U.S. 551 (1972) (No. 71-492) (arguing that pamphlets warrant press protections). There were a few peripheral-media litigants who focused solely on their speech
rights. See Brief of Petitioners and Cross-Respondents at 13–14, Int’l Soc. for Krishna
Consciousness, Inc. v. Lee, 505 U.S. 830 (1992) (Nos. 91-155, 91-339) (arguing that religious literature in airports is a permissible form of free speech); Brief of Respondent at 2,
Burson v. Freeman, 504 U.S. 191 (1992) (No. 90-1056) (advocating that the prohibition
of political literature in polling places is a burden on the right to free speech); Brief for
Petitioners at 10–11, Org. for a Better Austin v. Keefe, 402 U.S. 415 (1971) (No. 135) (arguing that pamphlets qualify for constitutional protections of free speech).
See, e.g., Brief for Appellants at 30, Turner Broad. Sys., Inc., 512 U.S. 622 (No. 93-44) (arguing that the laws in question “interfere[] with the editorial functions of the press”).
See, e.g., Brief of Appellant at 22, Fla. Star v. B.J.F., 491 U.S. 524 (1989) (No. 87-329) (saying that it is “the responsibility of the press to report” information regarding the commission of a crime involving actions of the government); Brief of Nat’l Citizens Comm. for

420

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW
260

[Vol. 11:2

261

ment,” “expos[ing] abuses of power,” and “engaging the public in
262
a ‘dialogue in ideas.’”
Furthermore, journalists and the press do
these things not for their own sake, but in serving as the “agent or
263
proxy of the public.” Like the Court then, the media litigants had a
vision of a journalist that valued the watchdog function and that involved more than the mere dissemination of content (i.e., speech).
Unlike the Court, however, the litigants would have secured additional protections against government restraints of press autonomy
and access.
In addition, the media litigants, collectively, were much more
faithful to the egalitarian, lonely-pamphleteer conception of the press
than was the Court. The Court reserved the press label for mainstream media, while the litigants saw themselves as essentially coequals. The mainstream litigants made no attempts to exclude
264
smaller media by urging recognition of ranks or tiers, and the peripheral media litigants were nearly unanimous in emphasizing the
commonalities among media and among communicators. As the litigants wrote in FEC v. Massachusetts Citizens for Life, Inc., “The liberty of
the press secured by the First Amendment is not the special province
of the traditional ‘institutional press,’ but is a fundamental right
265
which comprehends every sort of publication.”
IV. CONCLUSION
Despite thirty-five years of litigation and legislative action, the law
of newsgathering is still a contested and unsteady terrain in which
there are only a handful of loosely formed theoretical and doctrinal

260

261
262
263
264

265

Broad. et al. as Amici Curiae Supporting Respondents at 15, CBS Inc. v. FCC, 453 U.S.
367 (1981) (Nos. 80-207, 80-213, 80-214) (“[B]roadcasters have long had some responsibility to disseminate political speech.”).
Brief of Appellant at 24, Landmark Commc’ns, Inc. v. Virginia, 435 U.S. 829 (1978) (No.
76-1450) (quoting N.Y. Times v. United States, 403 U.S. 713, 717 (1971) (Black, J., concurring)).
Brief for Respondent at 16, City of L.A. v. Preferred Commc’ns, Inc., 476 U.S. 488 (1986)
(No. 85-390).
Brief for Appellees at 33, FCC v. League of Women Voters of Cal., 468 U.S. 364 (1984)
(No. 82-912) (quoting Neb. Press Ass’n v. Stuart, 427 U.S. 539, 547 (1976)).
Brief for Respondents at 36, Saxbe v. Wash. Post Co., 417 U.S. 843 (1974) (No. 73-1265).
See, e.g., Brief for Plaintiffs-Appellees at 63, USPS v. Council of Greenburgh Civic Ass’ns,
453 U.S. 114 (1981) (No. 80-608) (“The First Amendment was intended by the Founding
Fathers to be available to all, not merely to those who can bear great financial burdens
and project their press product in an imposing cover.”).
Brief for Appellee at 69, FEC v. Mass. Citizens for Life, Inc., 479 U.S. 238 (1986) (No. 85701).

Jan. 2009]

CONCEPTIONS OF PRESS FREEDOM

421

anchors. In the face of these ambiguities, both mainstream and peripheral journalists have urged lower courts to clarify and enlarge the
Supreme Court’s newsgathering jurisprudence. But those efforts
have often been derailed by mistrustful judges and lawmakers, many
of whom no doubt share the public’s disapproval of press perform266
ance and its pernicious assumption that mainstream journalists regard the First Amendment as a special manifest of rights that has
been set aside for, as Spiro Agnew put it, a “‘tiny and closed fraternity
267
of privileged men.’”
The results of this analysis show no support, however, for the abiding accusation that the media litigants have claimed an elite or preferred constitutional position, or that they have sought judicial recognition of a framework of special rights. It is true that the litigants
made some distinctions between speech and press, and between the
press and public. But they linked their claims to an egalitarian conception of the press in which the distinctions among communicators
were made on the basis of function, not identity.
The portrayal of mainstream journalists as disciples of Justice
Stewart who have sought to co-opt the Press Clause is still part of the
historical narrative about the news media’s constitutional cases, and it
is subtly reflected in popular critiques as well. It is plainly contradicted, however, by the briefs submitted to the Court. The litigants
did not attempt to bifurcate the First Amendment and to tie their
claims to particular clauses. And to the extent that they distinguished
speech and press, it was to separate expression and newsgathering,
not to establish an identity-based partition that would deny rights to
those lacking certain credentials or institutional affiliations. The litigants’ arguments were also anything but radical. They fit comfortably
under the rubric of the autonomy-model, which the Court has largely
endorsed as a matter of principle, even though it has lost track of it
on occasion.
The Court, meanwhile, has muddled this area of law by waffling
between the expression, autonomy, and special-rights models, by using the rhetoric of both the expert and egalitarian conceptions of the
press, and by not providing a clear basis for distinguishing freespeech and free-press controversies.

266

267

PROJECT FOR EXCELLENCE IN JOURNALISM, THE STATE OF THE NEWS MEDIA 2008: AN
ANNUAL
REPORT
ON
AMERICAN
JOURNALISM
(2008),
http://www.stateofthenewsmedia.com/2008/printable_overview_chapter.htm.
See Daniel Schorr, The Government’s Current War with the Free Press, CHRISTIAN SCI.
MONITOR, July 7, 2006, at 9.

422

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:2

Even more problematic from the media’s perspective is that the
Court has frequently mischaracterized the nature of special rights by
attaching that label to anything that benefits the press, irrespective of
how “press” is defined. The Court has also exacerbated misconceptions about the litigants’ claims by suggesting that they would require
the abandonment of long-standing neutrality principles or the application of exotic theories. In many cases in which the Court rejected
the litigants’ claims, however, the litigants were making logical extrapolations from the Court’s earlier rulings—often relying on
autonomy-model principles that the Court had previously embraced
but refused to revisit.
The fact that many of the litigants’ arguments flow directly from
the Court’s earlier opinions suggests that the two sides are not impossibly far apart. Going forward, if the Court could become slightly
more solicitous of the autonomy principles relied on by the litigants
in cases like Zurcher, Herbert, and Branzburg, and if the litigants could
allay some of the Court’s concerns by being even clearer about their
interest in protecting the core functions of the press and not the special status of the claimants, there will be some opportunity for a sensible reordering of press law and perhaps a reconciliation between
the media and the Court. Until then, those opposed to the broadening of press protections will no doubt continue repeating the familiar, if apocryphal, tales about the press’s brazen demands for special
rights, and in so doing, they will further impair the right of everyone
to gather and report news.