Skip navigation

Medina the Israeli Supreme Court Decision to Invalidate Prison Privatization

Download original document:
Brief thumbnail
This text is machine-read, and may contain errors. Check the original document to verify accuracy.
CONSTITUTIONAL LIMITS TO PRIVATIZATION: THE ISRAELI SUPREME COURT
DECISION TO INVALIDATE PRISON PRIVATIZATION
Barak Medina*
Abstract
The Israeli Supreme Court recently decided to strike down legislation to
establish a privately operated prison. The Court’s decision to invalidate this
legislation is interesting, as it stipulates that prison privatization is
unconstitutional per se, irrespective of its specific characteristics or expected
outcome. It ruled that executing governmental powers by prison staff employed
by a for-profit organization violates the prisoners’ basic rights to liberty and
human dignity. This essay discusses this position, and points out some of its
difficulties. It suggests that while the decision’s ultimate outcome can be
justified, it would have gained greater (normative) legitimacy if it were based on
a constitutional norm prohibiting the privatization of “core” governmental
powers rather than on an analysis of human rights.
INTRODUCTION ………………………………………………………………. 2
I. BACKGROUND: PRIVATIZATION AND THE ISRAELI CONSTITUTION …………. 3
II. PRIVATIZATION AND THE ENHANCED RISK OF ABUSE OF POWERS .………. 10
III. THE RIGHT NOT TO BE SUBJECT TO “PRIVATIZED” COERCIVE POWERS …. 16
1. Prison Privatization, Popular Legitimacy, and Social Meaning
2. The Court’s Reasoning
3. Critical Evaluation
IV. THE ROAD UNTAKEN: ENFORCING A CONSTITUTIONAL PROHIBITION
AGAINST PRISON PRIVATIZATION ……………………………………….. 30

*

Lawrence D. Biele Professor of Law and Dean, Faculty of Law, Hebrew University of Jerusalem, Israel.
msbmedina@mscc.huji.ac.il. I’m grateful to Alon Harel, Eyal Zamir, and participants at the British-Israeli
Legal Exchange meeting held at the UK Supreme Court in June 2010, for their helpful comments and
suggestions.

Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1700190

CONSTITUTIONAL LIMITS TO PRIVATIZATION

2

BARAK MEDINA

INTRODUCTION
The Israeli Supreme Court recently decided to strike down legislation to establish a
privately-operated prison.1 The Court’s decision to invalidate this legislation is
interesting, as it stipulates that despite the popularity of this practice in the democratic
world,2 prison privatization is unconstitutional per se, irrespective of its specific
characteristics or expected outcome. Moreover, while the academic literature on prison
privatization generally concentrates on the constraint against delegating governmental
powers to private entities,3 the Israeli Supreme Court ruled that executing governmental
powers by prison staff employed by a for-profit organization violates prisoners’ basic
rights to liberty and human dignity.
The eight to one decision is based on two main factors. The first, presented by two of
the Justices, is that a private entity employing governmental powers poses an unavoidable
risk of an unjustified use of force. According to this view, the very “culture” of for-profit
organizations creates a risk of an abuse of power. This risk is sufficiently high to classify
the privatization as an infringement of prisoners’ rights not to be subject to an unjustified
use of force or otherwise humiliating treatment by the prison guards. While this is a
consequentialist approach, as it points to the privatization’s expected outcome, the
Court’s analysis is profoundly non-empirical, but rather one that is based on axiomatic
assumptions about the outcomes of privatization.
1

HCJ 2605/05 The Human Rights Division, The Academic Center for Law and Business v. Minister of
Finance (November 19, 2009). An English translation is available at:
http://elyon1.court.gov.il/files_eng/05/050/026/n39/05026050.n39.pdf.
2

For a list of the dozens of countries in which private prisons operate see, e.g., Richard Harding, Private
Prisons, in 28 CRIME AND JUSTICE: A REVIEW OF RESEARCH 265, 268-69 (Michael H. Tonry ed., 2001).
Indeed, several scholars have pointed out that in recent years “the terms of the debate have shifted from
whether we should allow private prisons to how we can best manage them.” David Pozen, Managing a
Correctional Marketplace: Prison Privatization in the United States and the United Kingdom, 19 J. L. &
POL. 253, 256 (2003).
3

See, e.g., Ira P. Robbins, The Impact of the Delegation Doctrine on Prison Privatization, 35 UCLA L.
Rev. 911, 915 (1988) (the constitutionality of prison privatization under the delegation doctrine “is an
extremely close one, and it would not be surprising if a court were to rule against constitutionality.”);
Warren L. Ratliff, The Due Process Failure of American Prison Privatization Statutes, 30 SETON HALL L.
REV. 371 (1997); David N. Wecht, Breaking the Code of Deference: Judicial Review of Private Prisons, 96
YALE L.J. 815 (1987); Joseph E. Field, Making Prisons Private: An Improper Delegation of Governmental
Power, 15 HOFSTRA L. REV. 649 (1987). See also infra note 13.

Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1700190

CONSTITUTIONAL LIMITS TO PRIVATIZATION

3

BARAK MEDINA

The second reason, supported by all eight Justices of the majority, stipulates that an
inmate is entitled not to be subject to the use of coercive measures by employees of a
private, for-profit corporation. According to this view, the very act of implementing
incarceration powers by employees of a private entity infringes upon the inmates’ rights
to liberty and human dignity. This recognition of “a right against privatization” is the
central novelty of the Israeli Supreme Court’s decision.
This essay discusses these two positions, and points to some difficulties that each of
them involves. I suggest that while the decision’s ultimate outcome is justified, it would
have gained greater (normative) legitimacy if it were based on a constitutional norm
prohibiting the privatization of “core” governmental powers rather than on the analysis of
human rights. The essay starts, in part I, by briefly presenting the background of the
decision. It then moves on to discuss, in parts II and III, each of the two reasons
suggested by the Israeli Supreme Court. Section IV concludes, by discussing the
possibility of enforcing a constitutional prohibition against prison privatization.

I. BACKGROUND: PRIVATIZATION AND THE ISRAELI CONSTITUTION
Like other Western democracies, Israel has applied, in recent decades, a policy of
extensive privatization.4 This policy consists of three main elements: a shift from public
to private financing of the provision of several goods and services; empowerment of
private entities to produce goods and services that were previously produced by stateowned corporations; and the delegation of governmental powers to private persons. These
reforms aim mainly at providing better services at lower costs. In many areas, the reforms
have been successful, while in others the privatization has invoked intense ideological
and political debates.
From a legal perspective, implementing policies of privatization is (or was) generally
considered to be well within the powers of the Executive Branch. However, Israeli law
4

See, e.g., PRIVATIZATION AND INCREASING COMPETITION IN THE ISRAELI ECONOMY (JCPA and the Milken
Institute, 2000); AVI FIEGENBAUM, THE TAKE-OFF OF ISRAELI HIGH-TECH ENTREPRENEURSHIP IN THE
1990’S 33-48 (2007).

CONSTITUTIONAL LIMITS TO PRIVATIZATION

4

BARAK MEDINA

has some limitations to its power of privatization in the first element mentioned above—
the requirement of individuals to pay for the consumption of certain goods and services.
These limitations include mainly explicit provisions in legislation, which require the
government to publicly fund certain services (in areas such as education, health care, and
others), as well as some “social” rights, that are implicit in the right to human dignity
(including the right to elementary education, health, housing, and other aspects of “basic
living conditions”).5 Nevertheless, in other areas of privatization, Israeli law does not
restrict the government’s discretion. The law sets only procedural requirements to prevent
corruption and ensure efficiency, but does not impose limitations on the government’s
power to privatize state-owned corporations that provide services (such as transportation,
telecommunications, and so forth).6 The same used to be true regarding the delegation of
governmental powers to private persons.
The Israeli Constitution does not include any explicit provision that limits the powers
of the Knesset (Israeli parliament) or the government to delegate certain governmental
powers to private persons. Until the judgment discussed here, the existing precedents
suggested that the Executive Branch may delegate governmental powers to private
entities even without explicit legislative authorization. The legitimacy of such
privatization was subject only to process-based requirements, such as setting sufficient
guidelines by the relevant public entity, taking steps to prevent potential conflicts of
interests in the specific context, and implementing supervisory powers.7 In this respect,
the rule resembles the non-delegation doctrine of the U.S., which does not define specific

5

See, e.g., HCJ 366/03 Commitment to Peace and Social Justice Society and others v. Minister of Finance
(December 12, 2005). An English translation is available at:
http://elyon1.court.gov.il/files_eng/03/660/003/a39/03003660.a39.pdf. See, e.g., Yoram Rabin & Yuval
Shany eds., Economic, Social, and Cultural Rights in Israel (2004) (in Hebrew).
6

See, e.g., Aharon Barak, Israel Economic Constitution, 4 L. & GOVERNANCE 357 (2008) (in Hebrew);
Barak Medina, “Economic Constitution,” Privatization and Public Funding: A Framework of Judicial
Review of Economic Policy, in ITZCHAK ZAMIR BOOK ON LAW, GOVERNMENT AND SOCIETY 583, 648-52
(Yoav Dotan & Ariel Bendor eds., 2005) (in Hebrew).
7

See, e.g., FHCJ 5361/00 Falk v. Attorney General [2005] IsrSC 59(5) 145; HCJ 2505/90 Travel Agents
Association v. Minister of Transportation [1990] IsrSC 46(1) 543; HCJ 39/82 Henfling v. Mayor of Ashdod
[1982] IsrSC 36(2) 537. See also infra note 10.

CONSTITUTIONAL LIMITS TO PRIVATIZATION

5

BARAK MEDINA

functions as either properly or exclusively those of the government.8 Rather, the rule
employs the due-process clause only for protection against uncontrolled discretionary
power, and requires the private body to be guided by rules promulgated by governmental
agencies and subject to review by a public body.9 Accordingly, a considerably wide range
of governmental powers in Israel has been delegated to private persons and corporations
in recent years. These include: the serving of a custodial sentence by way of unpaid work
in private, not-for-profit institutions; the forcible hospitalization of mental patients in
private hospitals; the empowerment of various tax collection authorities to resort to the
assistance of private collection companies; the privatization of numerous security
services; the assignment of private sector lawyers as prosecutors; and the appointment of
private persons to serve in official planning and development committees.10
It should also be noted that this permissive approach towards privatization under
Israeli law was supplemented (and can be possibly explained) by the implementation of
the “quasi-public” entities doctrine. This doctrine subjects any body authorized to employ
governmental powers to the norms of public law, most importantly human rights laws, as
well as to the jurisdiction of the Israeli administrative courts, including the High Court of
Justice.11 Thus, the concern that was raised in the U.S., that since “private exercises of
government power are largely immune from constitutional scrutiny, …expanding
privatization poses a serious threat to the principle of constitutionally accountable
8

See, e.g., Dean Cass, Privatization: Politics, Law and Theory, 71 MARQ. L. REV. 449 (1988); Clayton P.
Gillette & Paul B. Stephan III, Constitutional Limitations on Privatization, 46 AM. J. COMP. L. 481, 482
(1998) (“it is hard to identify any function that, as a constitutional matter, has been characterized as
inherently public”); Paul R. Verkuil, Public Law Limitations on Privatization of Government Functions, 84
N.C.L. Rev. 397, 421-33 (2006). However, State law may impose such limits. A notable example is
California State Civil Service Act.
9

See Carter v. Carter Coal Co., 298 U.S. 238 (1936). For a modern statement of this doctrine see Todd &
Co. v. SEC, 557 F.2d 1008, 1012 (3d Cir. 1977), in which the court articulated a three-pronged test. For a
review see, e.g., Robbins, supra note 3.
10

The Supreme Court explicitly approved most of these delegations of powers to private entities. See, e.g.,
HCJ 1783/00 Haifa Chemicals Ltd v. Attorney-General [2003] IsrSC 57(3) 652 (legitimizing empowering
private lawyers to prosecute on behalf of the state); HCJFH 5361/00 Falk v. Attorney-General [2005] IsrSC
59(5) 145 (determining that there is no a priori conflict of interests in providing private persons with
governmental powers, such that decisions of this sort are subject only to specific factual proof of conflict of
interests).
11

See, e.g., HCJ 294/91 Jerusalem Burial Society v. Kastenbaum [1991] IsrSC 46(2) 464.

CONSTITUTIONAL LIMITS TO PRIVATIZATION

6

BARAK MEDINA

government,”12 is largely irrelevant in Israel’s case. The private exercising of government
power is subject not only to (the required) effective supervision by the Executive Branch,
but also to the judicially enforced duties set forth by public law norms. Under Israeli law,
the delegation of governmental powers to private persons hardly changes the formal
norms to which the power holder is subject.
Consequently, it was assumed that the government is authorized, at least in principle,
to empower private corporations to administer a prison. In line with the prevailing view
in other jurisdictions, prison privatization was assumed to meet the non-delegation
challenge as long as a public body provides sufficiently detailed guidelines for running
the prison, and applies effective supervisory powers.13 In addition, while in the U.S. the
applicability of constitutional scrutiny of private prisons is ambiguous,14 an outcome that
served several commentators to raise doubts about the constitutionality of the

12

Gillian E. Metzger, Privatization as Delegation, 103 COLUM. L. REV. 1367, 1373 (2003).

13

See, e.g., Pischke v. Litscher, 178 F.3d 497, 500 (7th Cir. 1999) (“[We] can[not] think of any …provision
of the Constitution that might be violated by the decision of a state to confine a convicted prisoner in a
prison owned by a private firm rather than by a government.”); Montez v. McKinna, 208 F.3d 862, 866
(10th Cir. 2000); White v. Lambert, 370 F.3d 1002, 1013 (9th Cir. 2004). See also Wecht, supra note 3, at
834 (“a reasoned application of non-delegation jurisprudence does not require a ban on prison privatization,
since the Court’s holdings do not derive from an Article I doctrine of per se invalidity.”); Robbins, supra
note 3, at 923-24 (“If a corrections agency promulgated rules of prison administration in the first instance,
…[and] control[s] over disciplinary proceedings …[or] make[s] de novo findings and an independent
decision on the violation and the penalty …courts would uphold delegations to private prison companies.”).
Robbins notes, however, that “the factual and philosophical differences between the private prison context
and the cases discussed may well motivate a court to hold that a statute authorizing a state to contract with a
private company to incarcerate its prisoners is unconstitutional.” Id. at 930. See also Connie Mayer, Legal
Issues Surrounding Private Operation of Prisons, 22 CRIM. L. BULL. 309, 320 (1986) (to avoid legal
challenge, it might be preferable for the state to maintain control over all disciplinary proceedings); Rachel
Christine Bailie Antonuccio, Prisons for Profit: Do the Social and Political Problems Have a Legal
Solution? 33 IOWA J. CORP. L. 577 (2008) (prisons privatization does not violates the non-delegation
doctrine).
14

On the one hand, in Richardson v. McKnight, 521 U.S. 399 (1997) the U.S. Supreme Court held that
private prison guards cannot claim qualified immunity in §1983; but on the other hand it ruled in
Correctional Services Corp. v. Malesko, 534 U.S. 61(2001) that companies operating private correctional
facilities are not subject to civil rights suits. See also Skelton v. Pri-Cor, Inc., 963 F.2d 100, 101-02 (6th
Cir. 1991); Rosborough v. Management and Training Corporation, 350 F.3d 459 (5th Cir. 2003). For a
discussion see, e.g., Alexander Volokh, Note, The Law of Prisons: III. A Tale of Two Systems: Cost,
Quality, and Accountability in Private Prisons, 115 HARV. L. REV. 1838, 1879-87 (2002); Lori DaCrosse,
Note, Richardson v. McKnight: Barring Qualified Immunity from 42 U.S.C. §1983 for Private Jailers, 26
PEPP. L. REV. 149 (1998). See also Ira P. Robbins, The Legal Dimensions of Private Incarceration, 38 Am.
U.L. Rev. 531, 577-604 (1989).

CONSTITUTIONAL LIMITS TO PRIVATIZATION

7

BARAK MEDINA

privatization,15 in Israel it was clear, as already indicated, that the private prison and its
staff will be subject to all public law norms.16 To remove doubts the government decided
to base the privatization on legislation and after intensive and lengthy discussions, the
Knesset enacted the Prisons Ordinance Amendment Law (no. 28), 2004. This Act
legitimizes the establishment of one prison, with 800 prisoners, managed by a private
corporation. The legislation, consisting of 54 sections, adopts the “British model” (The
Criminal Justice Act, 1991), with highly prescriptive contracts, multiple levels of
monitoring, and output-based evaluations. This model was chosen based on both the
above-mentioned legal doctrine in Israel regarding the legitimate delegation of
governmental powers to private entities, and the comparative experience that indicates
that this model yields superior performance from the private sector.17
The Act determines that the prison operator “is responsible for the proper
construction, management and operation of the privately managed prison, including: (1)
maintaining order, discipline and public security in the privately managed prison; (2)
preventing the escape of inmates that are held in custody in the privately managed prison;
and (3) ensuring the welfare and health of the inmates and taking steps during the
imprisonment that will aid their rehabilitation after their release from imprisonment,
including employment training and education” (Section 128.12). On the one hand, the
law empowers the employees of the private operator with most powers given to public
prison-guards. For instance, the private prison director is authorized, among other things,
to order an inmate to be held in administrative isolation for a maximum period of 48
hours, to order an external examination of the naked body of an inmate, and to approve
15

Robbins, supra note 14, at 604; Wecht, supra note 3, at 834-35; Metzger, supra note 12.

16

In its decision to invalidate the prison privatization the Israeli Supreme Court acknowledged that “the
concessionaire operaing the privately managed prison is subject to the judicial scrutiny of the High Court of
Justice and the rules of administrative law… . In view of this, and since the powers of the employees of the
private concessionaire are subject to restrictions parallel to those imposed on the powers of the officers of
the Israel Prison Service, we cannot determine that …the private concessionaire and its employees [are
allowed] to violate the human rights of inmates in the privately managed prison to a greater degree than the
violation of the human rights of inmates in a state managed prison.” HCJ 2605/05, supra note 1, para 41
(President Beinisch).
17

For a comparison between the UK and the US models in this context and a review of the research on the
performance of each model see, e.g., Pozen, supra note 2, at 271-84; RICHARD W. HARDING, PRIVATE
PRISONS AND PUBLIC ACCOUNTABILITY (1997).

CONSTITUTIONAL LIMITS TO PRIVATIZATION

8

BARAK MEDINA

the use of reasonable force in order to carry out the body search of an inmate. The private
prison guards are authorized to use reasonable force and take steps to restrain an inmate,
to use a weapon in order to prevent the escape of an inmate, and the power to carry out
the body search of an inmate. At the same time, the Act also imposes a long list of
restrictions. The Act explicitly states that an inmate held in a privately-managed prison
shall have the same rights, benefits and services as an inmate in a state-managed prison
(Section 128.11(3)(1)). It also requires all staff members to act according to the public
interest, respect inmates’ human rights, act reasonably and in accordance with public law
norms in general (128.31). All employees are formally subject to the provisions of the
Israeli Penal Code, 1977, which apply to civil servants (Section 128.9). In addition, the
law does not give the employees of the private operator the power to disciplinary
adjudication of inmates or the power to order an extension to the 48-hour period that an
inmate is held in administrative isolation. It determines the qualifications required to
serve as a staff member at the privatized prison, which are similar to those applied in
public prisons. Finally, the Act establishes a comprehensive supervisory scheme that
requires public-service supervisors to closely monitor the prison, empowers them to
revoke the contractor’s license to operate the prison (Sections 128.32-35), and imposes
the prison director to report immediately any use of coercive measures against a prisoner.
The government estimated that running the 800-prisoner facility by a private
corporation would enable substantial improvement of prisoners’ living conditions, while
saving the state approximately 350 million NIS (close to 100 million US dollars) over the
entire license period of 25 years.18 In response to the concern that this policy will have
adverse effects on prisoners, the supporters of this move pointed out that the privatization
of only one prison will serve as a pilot and an advisory committee, established by the Act,
18

HCJ 2605/05, supra note 1, para 47 (President Beinisch) (“The state… [argued that the privatization] is
expected to bring about a saving …which is estimated at approximately 20%-25% of the cost of operating a
prison, with similar standards, that is built and operated by the Israel Prison Service. According to this
opinion, the saving over the whole period of the concession is estimated at approximately NIS 290-350
million.”). For a discussion on the cost-benefit analysis of prisons privatization see, e.g., CHARLES H.
LOGAN, PRIVATE PRISONS: CONS AND PROS 76-118 (1990); Travis C. Pratt & Jeff Maahs, Are Private
Prisons More Cost-Effective than Public Prisons? A Meta-Analysis of Evaluation Research Studies, 45
CRIME & DELINQUENCY 358 (1999) (the empirical evidence regarding whether private prisons are more
cost-effective than public institutions, however, is inconclusive).

CONSTITUTIONAL LIMITS TO PRIVATIZATION

9

BARAK MEDINA

will collect data and analyze the consequences of this experiment before deciding
whether to expand this policy to other incarceration facilities or to cancel it altogether.
A petition challenging the constitutionality of the Act was filed to the Supreme Court
in 2005. The Court did not resolve the case for several years as proposals to repeal the
Act were discussed in the Knesset. Finally, in November 2009, after the legislation
proposals were not accepted, the Court ruled, in an eight to one decision, that the entire
amendment was invalid. This is the first time in Israel’s short history of judicial review of
legislation that an entire body of legislation, rather than specific provisions, was declared
invalid.
Before turning to the Court’s reasoning, it is important to add a few words on the
Israeli Constitution and the judicial review of legislation. Following the failure to create a
complete Constitution at the time of Israel’s foundation in 1948, the Knesset, which
serves as both the Legislative branch and as the Constitutive assembly, decided to create
a Constitution in a piece-mill process. Each part is titled “Basic-Law,” and the vision was
that when all chapters are enacted, they will be combined to form the Constitution. Over
the years, the Knesset enacted eleven Basic-Laws, including, in 1992, the Basic-Law:
Human Dignity and Liberty. However, the Knesset left some ambiguity (probably on
purpose) as to the legal status of these Basic-Laws in the interim period, before they are
combined to form the Constitution. The Basic-Laws include neither an explicit
“supremacy” clause nor enforcement mechanisms of their provisions over legislation. At
first, the Supreme Court held that only (the handful of) provisions in the Basic-Laws that
include explicit entrenchment clauses should be considered as limiting the legislature.
However, in 1995, in the Bank Mizrahi case, the Supreme Court changed course.19 It
ruled that even though the Basic-Law: Human Dignity and Liberty does not include an
entrenchment clause, its provisions bind the legislature. The decision was based mainly
on the inclusion of a “limitation clause” in this Basic-Law, which determines the
requirements that an act that infringes upon basic rights should fulfill. At that decision the
Court added that all Basic-Laws are the supreme law of the land, based on the view that
19

CA 6821/93 United Bank Ha’Mizrahi Ltd. v. Migdal [1995] IsrSC 49(4) 221.

CONSTITUTIONAL LIMITS TO PRIVATIZATION

10

BARAK MEDINA

the Knesset enjoys the powers of the Constitutional assembly, and every piece of
legislation that is titled “Basic-Law” is the product of employing constitutive powers.
However, in the years that followed this decision, the court almost entirely avoided
reviewing legislation on the basis of the infringement of provisions in non-human-rights
Basic-Laws. It is generally assumed that the lack of explicit “limitation clauses” in these
Basic-Laws makes it much less legitimate to base judicial review of legislation on these
provisions, both in terms of normative and popular legitimacy. Indeed, in the years
following the Bank Mizrahi decision, in all of the almost ten instances in which the Israeli
Supreme Court declared Acts of the Knesset invalid, the decision was based on the
findings that the legislation infringes upon a basic human right enumerated in the BasicLaw: Human Dignity and Liberty (or Basic-Law: Freedom of Occupation). Given this
background, it should come as no surprise that the Court’s analysis of the legitimacy of
prison privatization focused on claims of human rights violations. I return to this point in
part IV below.
As indicated, the Court’s decision consists of two main approaches. I begin with
presenting and evaluating the approach endorsed by Justices Procaccia and Naor.

II. PRIVATIZATION AND THE ENHANCED RISK OF ABUSE OF POWERS
A common argument against prison privatization concerns the dangers of excessive
and arbitrary use of force. The central claim is that private prisons would violate
prisoners’ human rights more often than public ones.20 Arguably, corporations can be
20

See, e.g., Ahmed A. White, Rule of Law and the Limits of Sovereignty: The Private Prison in
Jurisprudential Perspective, 38 AM. CRIM. L. REV. 111, 143 (2001) (“the intrusion of profit motives into
management decisions is a pervasive problem with private prisons… [It] encourages not only the
employment of under-trained and disinterested employees but aggregate reductions in staffing—practices
which in turn account in part for elevated levels of abuse, inmate-on-inmate violence.”). White suggests
that while “aggressive courts, competent legislatures, and zealous reformers theoretically could resolve all
the diverse problems that plague private prisons …the private prison seems a hopelessly problematic
institution.” Id. at 146. See also Sharon Dolovich, State Punishment and Private Prisons, 55 DUKE L. J.
439, 502 (2005) (“although existing oversight and accountability mechanisms are not wholly ineffectual,
they fall far short of providing adequate safeguards against prisoner abuse [in private prisons]”); Harold J.
Sullivan, Privatization of Corrections: A Threat to Prisoners’ Rights, in PRIVATIZING CORRECTIONAL
INSTITUTIONS 139 (Gary W. Bowman et al. eds., 1993).

CONSTITUTIONAL LIMITS TO PRIVATIZATION

11

BARAK MEDINA

expected to mistreat inmates in order to cut costs, or may cut back on labor expenses,
leaving inmates at the mercy of unscreened, untrained, understaffed, and underpaid
employees.21
The problem with these arguments is that they are not supported by the data collected
in countries that have adopted the policy of prison privatization, certainly those that have
applied the “British” model of intensive regulations and supervisions.22 It is also unclear
that the case-to-case judicial review of decision of the private prison authorities, even
when applying heightened judicial scrutiny,23 is insufficient to mitigate the risk of abuse.
Thus, while this concern may well justify imposing restrictions on the legitimate form of
prison privatization, and may even justify declaring invalid specific privatization
practices that have proved to excessively violate human rights, it cannot justify
determining that all prison privatization will cause an unjustified infringement of
prisoners’ human rights and is thus unconstitutional per se.
These concerns notwithstanding, two of the Justices in the Israeli Supreme Court,
Justices Procaccia and Naor, based their decision to invalidate the prison privatization
Act primarily on the view that the risk of harm posed by any form of prison privatization
is sufficiently high to justify declaring this policy invalid.
In their concurring opinions, Justices Procaccia and Naor based their position on an
assessment of the expected effect of the privatization on two types of rights, both of them
incorporated in the right to human dignity. First, inmates are entitled to the right to enjoy
21

For a review of the literature on the proposed contradiction between the provision of quality services and
the financial self-interests of private prison contractors see DAVID SHICHOR, PUNISHMENT FOR PROFIT 13565 (1995); Todd Mason, For Profit Jails: A Risky Business, in PRIVATIZING CORRECTIONAL INSTITUTIONS
163 (Gary W. Bowman et al. eds., 1993).
22

The empirical research is voluminous. For a review of the literature see, e.g., Pozen, supra note 2, at 281
(concluding that “[t]o the surprise of their critics and the satisfaction of their supporters, private prisons
have a reasonable track record in the United States and the United Kingdom so far”); Clifford J. Rosky,
Force, Inc.: The Privatization of Punishment, Policing, and Military Force in Liberal States, 36 CONN. L.
REV. 879, 946 (2004) (“the claim that private punishment violates human rights more often than public
punishment …has been vigorously and carefully contested, and there is very little empirical evidence to
support it.”). See also Logan, supra note 18, at 119-148; SHICHOR, supra note 21; Gaes et al., The
Performance of Privately Operated Prisons: A Review of Research, in PRIVATE PRISONS IN THE UNITED
STATES: AN ASSESSMENT OF CURRENT PRACTICE app. 2 (Douglas C. McDonald et al. eds., 1998).
23

Wecht, supra note 3, at 834-35.

CONSTITUTIONAL LIMITS TO PRIVATIZATION

12

BARAK MEDINA

some minimal living conditions, including reasonable physical space, food, health
services, and personal security, as well as the right to enjoy sufficient educational and
rehabilitation programs. Following these requirements is an essential element to what is
considered a legitimate form of punishment in a liberal democracy.24 Second, inmates are
entitled to the right not to be subject to an unjustified use of force or otherwise
humiliating treatment by the prison guards.
Justice Procaccia pointed out the two conflicting potential outcomes of prison
privatization. On the one hand, it may well improve prisoners’ living conditions in all
relevant aspects.25 This prediction can be based on a simple economic analysis. The
various dimensions of prisoners’ living conditions can be easily measured and monitored
by the state. As such, they are expected to be internalized by competing would-be private
contractors. Indeed, the experience in other countries supports this prediction.26 However,
Justice Procaccia added that, at the same time, privatization creates an enhanced risk of
abuse of the second type of rights mentioned above. This prediction, too, is based on an
evaluation of the contractor’s economic incentives. Presumably, it is notoriously difficult
to closely monitor private prison employees’ use of corrective measures against prisoners
and their daily attitudes towards prisoners.27 As a result, given the contractor’s purpose of
maximizing profits by minimizing operation costs, the likely result is an abuse of

24

HCJ 2605/05, supra note 1, para 33-34 (Justice Procaccia) (“When a person enters a prison, he loses his
liberty, but he does not lose his dignity. Providing a person’s basic needs, which is an absolute condition
for living with dignity, is also necessary for an inmate serving his sentence in prison, and the state is
obliged to provide them and allocate the necessary resources for this purpose. …Thus it has been
recognized that every prison inmate has a basic right to sleep on a bed …These basic needs are joined by
the needs for food and drink, clean clothes, fresh air, a minimum living space inside the prison and
responsible medical treatment. …The state is obligated to provide these basic living conditions for inmates
in its custody, and it must allocate the necessary budget for this purpose.”); para 2 (Justice Levy). See also,
e.g., Sharon Dolovich, Legitimate Punishment in Liberal Democracy, 7 BUFF. CRIM. L. REV. 307, 409-19
(2004); Brandon v. State Dep’t of Corr., 938 P.2d 1029, 1032 (Alaska 1997) (prisoners have a
constitutional right to rehabilitation).
25

HCJ 2605/05, supra note 1, para 18 (“Transferring the exercise of sovereign power to a private enterprise
…is likely to bring …social, economic and cultural benefits that serve the public interest in various
fields.”). See also id, para 29-38.
26

See, e.g., Pozen, supra note 2, at 281 (“Private prisons’ quality of service seems to have been particularly
high in the United Kingdom.”).
27

HCJ 2605/05, supra note 1, para 21.

CONSTITUTIONAL LIMITS TO PRIVATIZATION

13

BARAK MEDINA

prisoners’ right to human dignity.28 The contractor’s incentive schemes, and the lack of a
“civil-service” organizational culture, pose a considerable risk of violation of prisoners’
rights.29 Justice Naor also referred to this risk of abuse of power by the contractor,
mainly due to the lack of sufficient monitoring schemes.30
According to Justice Procaccia, the legitimacy of privatization hinges on whether the
privatization is in the prisoners’ best interests. She ruled that the required “balance” is
between the potential of providing prisoners with improved living conditions that go
beyond the minimum required by law, and the risk of violating the “core” of prisoners’
right to human dignity.31 Justice Procaccia held that the latter risk of privatization
outweighs the former potential benefits and thus, found that privatization unjustifiably
infringes upon prisoners’ right to human dignity, and declared it invalid.32 She ruled that
“the potential harm that is inherent in the privatization of a sovereign authority is integral

28

Id. para 16 (“The involvement of an improper and irrelevant consideration in the exercise of sovereign
coercive authority in the criminal proceeding creates a real potential risk of a distortion of the proper
balance between the need to use power to achieve a purpose in the public interest and the protection of the
human rights of the individual.”).
29

Id. para 18-20 (“The balance and restraint in the exercise of enforcement power …cannot be relied upon
in the hands of a party that is not an organ of the state. …The private enterprise …has never internalized the
doctrine of balances in the exercise of sovereign power… The mechanisms of training, education,
supervision and discipline that are built into the civil service for its employees, and which define the rules
of exercising sovereign power, do not apply to it. … [A] real concern arises that transferring [coercive
powers] to a private enterprise will result in disproportionate harm to the individual, which may make such
a transfer illegitimate.”).
30

Id. para 16 (“the disparities in knowledge between the concessionaire and the state, despite its
supervisory role, may be abused for the self-interest of the concessionaire and to the detriment of the
inmates in its custody.”). See also id. para 15 (“[Private operator] is tainted by an inherent conflict of
interests in exercising sovereign authority, because it is an entity that is motivated by considerations of
profit, which are improper considerations when exercising a sovereign power regarding the imposition of
imprisonment and the manner in which it is imposed. This is an a priori conflict of interests that does not
require any specific factual proof.”).
31
32

Id. para 50.

Id, para 50 (“Achieving an improvement in prison conditions, although important, cannot outweigh the
potential violation of the core rights of prison inmates, which is inherent in giving power to the private
concessionaire to exercise sovereign authority over individuals under its control. In a democratic
constitutional state, the price of enhancing the welfare of a person should not be paid in a manner that
causes a possible violation of his core human rights.”).

CONSTITUTIONAL LIMITS TO PRIVATIZATION

14

BARAK MEDINA

to it and of such a degree that it does not allow for a process of experimentation and
arriving at conclusions in consequence thereof.”33
This position raises several difficulties. First, it substantially expands the definition of
an “infringement” of basic liberty to encompass acts that merely have the potential to
inflict harm, which is uncertain. Exposing a person to the risk of harm should be
classified as an infringement of rights only if the magnitude of the risk, in terms of the
type of harm and the likelihood of its realization, exceeds some substantial threshold.34
There is clearly a basis for concern that the private operator’s incentive schemes will
induce an abuse of power; and one cannot easily dismiss the possibility of an ineffective
regulation, for instance, due to “capture” or the lack of expertise in the civil service when
the state does not take part in administering prisons.35 However, the scope of the risk that
prison guards at a private prison will use unjustified force or that they will humiliate
prisoners, are empirical and should be determined by a detailed examination of the
specific provisions of the legislation, the scope of monitoring powers of the supervisors,
and so forth. As already argued above, the data collected thus far in other countries do not
support the view that the risk of harm to prisoners’ rights is sufficiently high to
characterize any prison privatization as a human rights violation.36 This is especially true
given the comprehensive supervisory mechanisms implemented in Israeli law.37

33

Id. para 51. See also id. para 25-26 (Justice Naor).

34

See, .e.g, Frank Jackson & Michael Smith, Absolutist Moral Theories and Uncertainty, 103 J. PHIL. 267
(2006); Ron Aboodi, Adi Borer, and David Enoch, Deontology, Individualism, and Uncertainty: A Reply to
Jackson and Smith, 105 J. PHIL. 259 (2008). Cf. David McCarthy, Rights, Explanation, and Risks, 107
ETHICS 205, 208-12 (1997) (imposing even low-probability risks infringes (moral) rights).
35

See, e.g. Pozen, supra note 2, at 282 (“[W]hile private prisons have performed respectably in the
aggregate, their results have been highly inconsistent—including the troubling examples of riots in several
U.S. private prisons and abuses …in the United Kingdom. Rather than be seen as outliers, these
breakdowns in prison management should be seen as indicative of the risks of contracting.”).
36
37

See supra note 22.

See HCJ 2605/05, supra note 1, para 42 (President Beinisch) (“These supervisory mechanisms, which are
apparently more comprehensive than the supervisory mechanisms that exist in other countries where private
prisons operate in a similar format, are prima facie capable of reducing the concern that the violation of
human rights in the privately managed prison will be greater than that in the prisons of the Israel Prison
Service. …[W]e should assume that the supervisory mechanisms provided in the amendment will operate
properly; in any case, the arguments with regard to the manner of exercising them are the kind of arguments
that are more suited to being examined in an administrative petition than in a constitutional one.”). See also

CONSTITUTIONAL LIMITS TO PRIVATIZATION

15

BARAK MEDINA

Second, the characterization of the expected improvement in prisoners’ living
conditions to exceed the “minimum required” is debated. As pointed out by Justice Levy
in his dissent, the current living conditions in Israel’s prisons is far from satisfactory.38
Justice Procaccia conceded that given the current budget limits,39 and the fact that current
and would-be prisoners fail to form an effective interest group, an improvement is likely
only through privatization.40 Justice Procaccia’s position does not address the challenge
that even if prisoners’ current living conditions met the minimum set by law, they would
fall below the requirement set by the human rights law.41 Indeed, a decision that
privatization is required in order to terminate the continuing infringement of inmates’
right to human dignity might be interpreted as an acknowledgement not only of the public
prisons’ failure, but also of the Court’s inability to remedy this lasting injustice.
However, this concern cannot justify the result of placing so little weight on the potential
benefit of privatization. It seems that once the Court was willing to concede that a
substantial improvement in living conditions cannot be expected in the near future other
than through privatization, a greater weight should have been assigned to the expected
benefits of privatization in comparison to its expected risks.

id. para 5 (Justice Levy, dissent) (“prospective constitutional scrutiny is possible only when there is a high
probability …that the assumptions underlying it will be realized. …This is the reason why I have difficulty
in reconciling myself to a position that is based on a potential violation of rights, when the chances that it
will occur are not currently known.”).
38

Id. para 3 (“at the present, because of budgetary and other crises, the subject of imprisonment finds itself
frequently relegated to a low place in the order of the government’s priorities.”). See also Uri Timor,
Privatization of Prisons in Israel: Gains and Risks, 39 Isr. L. Rev. 81, 100 (2006).
39

HCJ 2605/05, supra note 1, para 32 (“The significant increase in the number of prison inmates and
persons held under arrest in Israel, the serious long-term security problems that result in an increase in the
number of security prisoners and detainees, the rise in serious crimes and the escalating number of foreign
workers and illegal aliens held under arrest until they are deported have all significantly increased the need
for the resources and means required to maintain prison facilities to the required standards. …[I]t is hard to
find the additional resources needed to improve the welfare of prison inmates.”).
40

Id. para 34 (“In the complex reality of social life in Israel, with its many essential needs, giving
budgetary preference to improving the welfare of the prison inmate beyond the basic standards required by
law is not assured.”). It should also be added that prisons privatization may indirectly induce improvements
in the inmates’ living conditions in public prisons too, through the greater public attention that the
operation of private prisons attract. Logan, supra note 18, at 256-57.
41

See supra note 24.

CONSTITUTIONAL LIMITS TO PRIVATIZATION

16

BARAK MEDINA

Lastly, given the assumption that the purpose of privatization is to enhance prisoners’
interests, such that the question is what its net expected effect would be, employing strict
judicial review of the legislation in this case is hard to justify. There has been no claim
that the legislature disregarded inmates’ legitimate interests or decided the issue without
sufficient research and consideration.42 The required assessment is merely what the actual
expected outcome of privatization on inmates’ interests and welfare is, and the Court
should have shown greater deference to the legislature. The risks may or may not
materialize, as the conflicting data from other countries indicate, and the expected
improvement in living conditions may or may not outweigh the risk. It is unclear what is
the basis of preferring the Court’s prior assessment in this regard over that of the political
branches.43

III. THE RIGHT NOT TO BE SUBJECT TO “PRIVATIZED” COERCIVE POWERS
1. Prison Privatization, Popular Legitimacy, and Social Meaning
An alternative argument that has been made in the academic literature against prison
privatization (and against the privatization of other uses of force, such as policing and
military force) points to the effect of privatization on the social meaning of punishment
and thus on its (normative) legitimacy.44 This argument too starts with the premise that
unlike the government, private corporations who run prisons pursue profits. However, the
alleged concern does not focus on a prediction of the different outcomes of private and

42

Cf. Linda G. Cooper, Minimizing Liability with Private Management of Correctional Facilities, in
PRIVATIZING CORRECTIONAL INSTITUTIONS 131 (Gary W. Bowman et al. eds., 1993) (governments who
privatize prisons are not interested in safeguarding the rights of inmates but rather in promoting popular
agendas and cutting costs); Rosky, supra note 22, at 944-49.
43

See HCJ 2605/05, supra note 1, para 9 (Justice Levy, dissent). It should be noted that President Beinisch,
who delivered the opinion of the Court, was probably aware of this difficulty, and stated that the social
benefit of the privatization is merely economic saving. She thus ruled that the Court should avoid
presenting the required scrutiny as a balance between the inmates’ competing interests. Id. para 68 (“[T]he
balancing formula proposed by my colleague Justice Procaccia, …undermine[s] to a large degree the
manner in which the limits of permitted violations of human rights are defined …because it may be
assumed that in a considerable number of cases …it will also be possible to ‘translate’ the value of public
interest that is weighed on the scales against the violated human right into another human right.”).
44

For a clear presentation and evaluation of this argument see Rosky, supra note 22, at 963-70.

CONSTITUTIONAL LIMITS TO PRIVATIZATION

17

BARAK MEDINA

public prisons, but rather on the symbolic or communicative aspect of incarceration.
Presumably, liberal states impose sanctions not only to stop crimes, but also to send a
message about the “public nature” of the punishment: “The badge of the arresting police
officer, the robes of the judge, and the state patch of the corrections officer are symbols
of the inherently public nature of crime and punishment.”45
The claim is that implementing sanctions through private prisons conveys the wrong
message of the practice of incarceration. The exercise of power by employees of a forprofit organization conveys a social meaning of “commodification” of the use of force,
and that inmates in a private prison are only a means to an end.46 It is also suggested that
privatization places cultural “distance” between the use of force and the citizens of the
liberal state.47 This “distance” too, conveys a social meaning of disrespect to prisoners.48

45

John DiIulio, Jr., The Duty to Govern: a Critical Perspective on the Private Management of Prisons and
Jails, in PRIVATE PRISONS AND THE PUBLIC INTEREST 155, 173 (Douglas C. McDonald ed., 1990). See also
id.: “[T]he message ‘Those who abuse liberty shall live without it’ …ought to be conveyed by the offended
community of law-abiding citizens, through its public agents, to the incarcerated individual. The
administration of prisons and jails involves the legally sanctioned coercion of some citizens by others. This
coercion is exercised in the name of the offended public.” See also Ira P. Robbins, Privatization of
Corrections: Defining the Issues, 40 VAND. L. REV. 813, 827 (1987) (“[The] symbolic question may be the
most difficult policy issue of all for privatization: Who should operate our prisons and jails …assuming that
prisoners and detainees will retain no fewer rights and privileges than they had before the transfer to private
management? In an important sense, this is really part of the constitutional-delegation issue, in that it could
be argued that virtually anything that is done in a total, secure institution by the government or its designee
is an expression of government policy, and therefore should not be delegated.”).
46

Michael Walzer, At McPrison and Burglar King It's …Hold the Justice, NEW REPUBLIC, April 8, 1985, p.
11.
47

Id.; White, supra note 20, at 139 (“Private prisons tend to distance public officials from responsibility for
the way private prisons are run.”). See also Jon D. Michaels, Beyond Accountability: The Constitutional,
Democratic, and Strategic Problems with Privatizing War, 82 WASH. U. L. Q. 1001, 1008 (2004) (pointing
at the practice of “tactical privatization,” which is motivated “by a desire to alter substantive policy: Private
agents would be used to achieve public policy ends that would not otherwise be attainable, were the
government confined to relying exclusively on members of the U.S. Armed Forces. …[Privatization helps]
to elude public debate, circumvent Congress’s coordinate role in conducting military affairs, and evade
Security Council dictates…”).
48

Walzer, id. at 12-13. A related moral, rather than cultural argument is offered by Alon Harel, who argues
that private prison guards, but not public ones, are (morally) required to employ discretion about the
legitimacy of depriving inmates of their right to freedom. Consequently, private entities which imprison
people should not be regarded merely as executing or implementing public decisions, but instead as ones
that employ their own private judgements concerning the justness of the sanctions they inflict. Alon Harel,
Why Only the State May Inflict Criminal Sanctions: The Case Against Privately Inflicted Sanctions, 14
LEGAL THEORY 113 (2008).

CONSTITUTIONAL LIMITS TO PRIVATIZATION

18

BARAK MEDINA

This type of arguments raises several difficulties. First, the claim that the lack of
“social” legitimacy deprives the practice of incarceration of its normative legitimacy is
not explained. It is not clear what exactly the social message that the inflicting of
punishment should convey as a prerequisite for its legitimacy.49 Second, even if one
could establish some kind of such an essential symbolic message50 or “social meaning” to
punishment,51 it has not been established that a prison operated by a private corporation
necessarily conveys the wrong message.52 Arguably, the social meaning of punishment is
shaped primarily by the role of the “public” in deciding on the sanctions and regulations
of the prisons, and much less by the identity of the entity, which operates the prison.53
Third, assuming that one may attribute some “cultural” or even moral deficiency in
private prisons, the arguments suggested thus far in the academic literature do not specify
any established constitutional doctrine that can be used to (legally) invalidate such a
policy.
The decision of the Israeli Supreme Court aims to provide this missing link between
the cultural and ethical theories and constitutional law. According to the Court’s
approach, the symbolic social meaning of the privatization of the power to incarcerate
amounts to an infringement of prisoners’ rights to liberty and human dignity, and since

49

See Rosky, supra note 22, at 965 (n. 316) (“Commodification critics rarely trouble themselves to spell
out normative conclusions and principles—to explain why the social meaning of punishment, policing, and
military force is, or should be, important. …Social meaning does not stand alone; it stands alongside
countless other serious compelling concerns. …In lieu of such arguments, cultural critics normally proffer
canned assumptions and assertions that exercises of punishment, policing, and military force ‘must’ send
public messages.”).
50

For such attempts see, e.g., R.A. DUFF, TRIALS AND PUNISHMENTS 233-62 (1986) (the aim of punishment
should be to censure offenders, in such a way as to provide them an opportunity for moral reform.
Punishment must aim at the rational moral persuasion of offenders, convincing them to repent their
wrongdoing and reunite with the community); Jean Hampton, Correcting Harms Versus Righting Wrongs:
The Goal of Retribution, 39 UCLA L.R. 1659 (1992) (the aim of punishment is to symbolically nullify the
demeaning messages conveyed by certain types of wrongdoing and reaffirm the victim’s equal value).
51

Rosky, supra note 22, at 966 (“Liberal societies police and punish criminals to proclaim that crime is
wrong and the social contract is right. …These social meanings are vital social resources; they are a large
part of what binds us together and makes us behave. When we exercise punishment, …we strengthen the
cultural foundations of our political, legal, economic, and social systems.”).
52

Richard L. Lippke, Thinking About Private Prisons, 16 CRIM. JUST. ETHICS 26, 35 (1997) (“private
prisons [too] might be able to convey the right sort of message.”); Rosky, supra note 22, at 967-70.
53

Rosky, id. at 967-68.

CONSTITUTIONAL LIMITS TO PRIVATIZATION

19

BARAK MEDINA

the state cannot show a compelling public interest in privatization, such a policy is
invalid.
President Beinisch, who delivered the opinion of the Court, explicitly acknowledged
that it was not sufficiently established that the operation of private prisons would
necessarily result in more severe harm to inmates’ basic rights, in comparison to public
prisons.54 The Court ruled that privatization is illegitimate based on the principle that the
state, through its organs, must maintain its monopoly on the use of force and may not
delegate this power to private entities. The authorization of private persons, who are not
part of the public service, to employ coercive powers such as those granted to prison
guards is illegitimate per se, regardless of the actual or expected use of these powers by
such persons.55
2. The Court’s Reasoning
The Court ruled that a person is entitled, in addition to the right not to be incarcerated
(as part of the right to liberty), to the independent right not to be incarcerated in a private
prison.56 The Court’s decision that a person is entitled to the latter right, which is
classified as part of both the right to liberty and to human dignity, is based on two main
54

HCJ 2605/05, supra note 1, para 67 (“[N]o adequate probative basis has been brought before us for a
judicial decision regarding the potential violation that [the prison privatization law] may cause to the human
rights of inmates in the privately managed prison in comparison to the state prisons; certainly no sufficient
basis was established in order for us to determine that there exists the [required] degree of likelihood,
namely ‘a near certainty that when realized will materially and seriously violate a constitutional basic
right.’”); id. at para 47 (“A[t] this stage of the ‘privatization’ planning process, we [are un]able to determine
that [it] is not prima facie capable of realizing the purposes of an economic saving and improving the
prisons conditions of inmates that it was designed to achieve.”).
55

Id. para 67 (“[M]y position regarding the unconstitutionality of [the prison privatization law] is not based
on a potential violation of human rights caused by the provisions of the amendment, but on the actual
violation of the constitutional rights to personal liberty and human dignity caused by the provisions of the
amendment themselves, irrespective of the manner in which they will actually be implemented.”).
56

The Court stated that a person’s right to liberty is infringed not only by the criminal court’s decision to
imprison that a person, but also by the execution of this decision. Id. para 25 (President Beinisch) (“Indeed,
from a normative viewpoint, the decision of the competent courts of the state to sentence a particular person
to imprisonment is the source of the power to violate the constitutional right of that individual to personal
liberty. But the actual violation of the right to personal liberty takes place on a daily basis as long as he
remains an inmate of the prison. This violation of the right to personal liberty is inflicted by the party that
manages and operates the prison where the inmate is held in custody, and by the employees of that party,
whose main purpose is to ensure that the inmate duly serves the term of imprisonment to which he has been
sentenced …and complies with the rules of conduct in the prison, which also restrict his personal liberty.”).

CONSTITUTIONAL LIMITS TO PRIVATIZATION

20

BARAK MEDINA

grounds—the “democratic legitimacy” of imposing sanctions, and the symbolic effect of
private incarceration on the status of the inmate.
According to the first reason, employing coercive powers by persons who are not
employed by state organs lacks “democratic legitimacy.” The (popular) legitimacy of the
use of force is subject to the constraint that the power-holder aims, as an institutional
matter, to promote the social interest rather than some private interest. In the words of
President Beinisch:57
“[T]he democratic legitimacy for the use of force …relies on the fact that
organized force exercised by and on behalf of the state is what causes the
violation of …rights. Were this force not exercised by the competent organs
of the state, in accordance with the powers given to them and in order to
further the general public interest rather than a private interest, this use of
force would not have democratic legitimacy, and it would constitute de facto
an improper and arbitrary use of violence.”58
This position, that only the exercising of criminal sanctions (and the use of force in
general) by state organs gains sufficient “democratic” or popular legitimacy, seems to be
based on two related positions: the enhanced risk that the authority to use force will be
abused by persons who whose employer is not a state organ;59 and the concern that the
exercising of criminal sanctions by private persons will convey the wrong social message
of the act of inflicting punishment.60 It is not clear whether the Court endorsed these
57

Id. para 26.

58

See also id. para 20 (Justice Procaccia) (“The exercise of coercive authority by a party that is not the
state, which violates core human rights, necessarily does not enjoy the confidence and acceptance of
society. It lacks social, moral and constitutional legitimacy.”); id. para 27.
59

Id. para 26 (President Beinisch) (“The fact that the organized force is exercised by a body that acts
through the state and is subject to the laws and norms that apply to anyone who acts through the organs of
the state and also to the civil service ethos in the broad sense of this term is capable of significantly
reducing the danger that the considerable power given to those bodies will be abused, and that the invasive
powers given to them will be exercised arbitrarily or in furtherance of improper purposes. …[S]ince those
bodies act within the framework of the democratic political mechanism and are subject to its rules, their
legitimacy is enhanced.”).
60

Id. para 29 (President Beinisch) (“[W]hen the state …denies the personal liberty of an individual—in
accordance with the sentence that is imposed on him by a competent court—it thereby discharges its basic
responsibility as sovereign for enforcing the criminal law and furthering the general public interest. By

CONSTITUTIONAL LIMITS TO PRIVATIZATION

21

BARAK MEDINA

positions. On the one hand, it explicitly stated, as already indicated, that “[t]he
independent violation of the constitutional right to personal liberty of inmates in a
privately managed prison exists even if we assume that from a factual-empirical
viewpoint it has not been proved that inmates in that prison will suffer worse physical
conditions and invasive measures than those in the public prisons.”61 The Court’s position
may thus be that popular legitimacy of prison privatization is a precondition for its
normative legitimacy, and the former is shaped according to popular perceptions (rather
than those of the Court) of the expected outcome of such a policy. On the other hand, the
Court refers extensively to the state’s obligations to maintain exclusive control over the
prisons according to the “social contract.”62 This may indicate an objective, normative
approach, rather than merely a popular one, about the legitimate form of punishment.
The second reason that the Court gave for the position that a person is entitled to an
independent right not to be incarcerated in a private prison is the symbolic aspects of the
interaction between the private prison guards and the inmate. The Court noted that “we
should take into account not merely that person’s actual loss of personal liberty for a
certain period, but also the manner in which he is deprived of liberty,”63 and ruled that
“the existence of a privately managed prison …inherently [violates] the human dignity of
prison inmates.”64 The basis for this position resembles the argument mentioned above,

contrast, when the power to deny the liberty of the individual is given to a private corporation, the
legitimacy of the sanction of imprisonment is undermined, since the sanction is enforced by a party that is
motivated first and foremost by economic considerations—considerations that are irrelevant to the
realization of the purposes of the sentence, which are public purposes.”).
61

Id. para 30 (President Beinisch). See also supra note 54.

62

See, e.g., id. para 23 (President Beinisch) (“Although, naturally, many changes and developments have
occurred since the seventeenth century in the way in which the nature and functions of the state are
regarded, it would appear that the basic political principle that the state …is responsible for public security
and the enforcement of the criminal law has remained unchanged…, and it is a part of the social contract on
which the modern democratic state is also based.”); id. para 2 (Justice Arbel) (“The transfer of these
functions from the state to a private enterprise undermines the justification that underlies the exercising of
the power and amounts to a refusal by the state, albeit only a partial one, to play ‘its part’ in the social
contract. It makes the state a bystander that does not seek to realize independent goals of its own.”); id. para
2-4 (Justice Hayut); id. para 4 (Justice Procaccia); and more.
63

Id. para 30 (President Beinisch).

64

Id. para 37 (President Beinisch).

CONSTITUTIONAL LIMITS TO PRIVATIZATION

22

BARAK MEDINA

about the alleged “commodification” of the use of force, and that in private prisons
inmates are treated inevitably as only a means to an end:65
“Imprisoning persons in a privately managed prison leads to a situation in
which the clearly public purposes of the imprisonment are blurred and diluted
by irrelevant considerations that arise from a private economic purpose,
namely the desire of the private corporation operating the prison to make a
financial profit. There is therefore an inherent and natural concern that
imprisoning inmates in a privately managed prison …turns the prisoners into
a means whereby the corporation that manages and operates the prison makes
a financial profit. It should be noted that the very existence of a prison that
operates on a profit-making basis reflects a lack of respect for the status of the
inmates as human beings, and this violation of the human dignity of the
inmates does not depend on the extent of the violation of human rights that
actually occurs behind the prison walls.”66
The Court referred to the approach offered by Meir Dan-Cohen, according to whom
“as long as certain actions are generally considered to express disrespect, one cannot
knowingly engage in them without offending against the target’s dignity, no matter what
one’s motivations and intentions are.”67 The Court added that “a violation of [the right to]
human dignity [occurs] …when a certain act that is done or a certain institution that is
created reflects an attitude of disrespect from a social viewpoint towards the individual
and his worth as a human being.”68 It found such an “attitude of disrespect” in the context
of prison privatization:69

65

Id. para 36 (President Beinisch).

66

See also id. at para 51 (“Imprisonment that is based on a private economic purpose turns the inmates,
simply by imprisoning them in a private prison, into a means whereby the …operator of the prison can
make a profit; thereby, not only is the liberty of the inmate violated, but also his human dignity.”); id. para
3-5 (Justice Arbel); id. para 18 (Justice Naor).
67

MEIR DAN-COHEN, HARMFUL THOUGHTS: ESSAYS ON LAW, SELF, AND MORALITY 162 (2002).

68

HCJ 2605/05, supra note 1, para 38 (President Beinisch).

69

Id. para 39 (President Beinisch).

CONSTITUTIONAL LIMITS TO PRIVATIZATION

23

BARAK MEDINA

“When the state transfers the power to imprison someone, with the
invasive powers that go with it, to a private corporation that operates on a
profit-making basis, this action—both in practice and on an ethical and
symbolic level—expresses a divestment of a significant part of the state’s
responsibility for the fate of the inmates, by exposing them to a violation of
their rights by a private profit-making enterprise. This conduct of the state
violates the human dignity of the inmates of a privately managed prison, since
the public purposes that underlie their imprisonment and give it legitimacy
are undermined, and …their imprisonment becomes a means for a private
corporation to make a profit. This symbolic significance derives, therefore,
from the very existence of a private corporation that has been given powers to
keep human beings behind bars while making a financial profit from their
imprisonment.”
Finally, the Court emphasizes that this symbolic “injury, caused by the exercise
of authority over an inmate by an employee of a private company, …is not an
injury that derives from the subjective feelings of those inmates, but an objective
violation of their constitutional right to human dignity.”70
Given the decision that privatization infringes upon prisoners’ basic liberties,
the Court examined whether this infringement meets the proportionality
requirement. It held that the harm to prisoners’ basic rights outweighs the expected
benefit of operating private prisons,71 and thus declared the Act invalid and
prohibited the operation of a prison by a private corporation.

70
71

Id. para 37 (President Beinisch).

Id. para 52-55 (President Beinsich). It should be noted that while Justice Procaccia accepted the claim
that the purpose of the privatization, and hence its social benefit, is to improve the prisoners’ living
conditions (see supra Part II), President Beinisch ruled that the social benefit is merely economic saving:
id. para 54, 68 (“I do not think that in the circumstances of the case …it is possible to hold that improving
the welfare of the prison inmates is the [privatization’s] main purpose. …The purpose of improving the
welfare of prison inmates …could have been achieved without any need for any normative change.”). See
also supra note 43.

CONSTITUTIONAL LIMITS TO PRIVATIZATION

24

BARAK MEDINA

3. Critical Evaluation
In my opinion, the Court’s reasons are susceptible to the difficulties that were
raised against similar arguments, as discussed above. In what follows, I try to
evaluate the Court’s decision from two main perspectives—the position that if
incarcerating a person in a private prison lacks social legitimacy and conveys a
symbolic message of disrespect toward the inmates, it amounts to an infringement
of the inmate’s rights to liberty and human dignity; and the view that private prison
lacks social legitimacy and disrespects inmates.
I start with the first, more general perspective. The decision reflects an
important development in human rights law. According to the prevailing approach,
the concept of human rights deals primarily with a person’s actual and concrete
interests. The classification of a certain interest as a “human right” is often based on
some normative, objectively defined reasons, but such a classification requires the
relevant interest to also be significant to the individual, the right-holder. The Israeli
Supreme Court’s decision expands this definition as it holds that an inmate also has
an interest, which is classified as a human right, that the discretion what specific
measures will be used against him or her (for instance, to maintain order in the
prison) will be employed by organs of the state and not by private entities.
To inquire this concept, consider the following two examples. The first deals with the
status of intention. Is there a right not to be subject to intended harm, which is
distinguished from the more general right not to be harmed?72 According to the more
traditional view, which reflects a consequentialist approach, a person is entitled simply to
the right not to be harmed, be the actor’s subjective intentions or the act’s objective
purposes as they may. In contrast, a deontological approach calls for a distinction. For
instance, the scope of protection of the right not to be subject to intended harm is

72

For different positions in this debate (and references to many more discussions), see Judith Jarvis
Thomson, Physician Assisted Suicides: Two Moral Arguments, 109 ETHICS 497, 514-16 (1999);
David Enoch, Intending, Foreseeing, and the State, 13 LEGAL THEORY 69, 79-81 (2007); William J.
Fitzpatrick, Acts, Intentions, and Moral Permissibility: In Defence of the doctrine of Double Effect, 63
ANALYSIS 317 (2003); Joseph Shaw, Intentions and Trolleys, 56 PHIL. Q. 63 (2006).

CONSTITUTIONAL LIMITS TO PRIVATIZATION

25

BARAK MEDINA

significantly different from the right not to be subject to unintended harm.73 In some
cases, the latter interest is not even classified as a human right. For instance, consider the
status of omission: while an intended omission by the state, in which the state
intentionally avoids taking steps that could have saved a person’s life, may well be
considered as an infringement of the victim’s right to life, an unintended omission that
leads to the same fatal outcome is typically not classified as an infringement.74 Even if,
from the victim’s subjective perspective, the actor’s intention or the act’s purpose may be
irrelevant, as what matters to her may be only the act’s ultimate outcome, there may still
be a normative distinction here.
The second example that I suggest considering is the status of authorization by law.
Should there be a distinction between the right not to be harmed by an act that was
decided by the Executive Branch, without an explicit authorization by parliament, and the
right not to be harmed by the same act that was explicitly determined by legislation? The
right-holder may be indifferent to the two cases, while from a normative, objective
perspective we may well justify taking into account the process of deciding on the act.
It seems that there is an important difference between the two examples. In the first
example only, the objective principle or standard should be incorporated into the
definition of the right itself. The basis of distinction may be the linkage between the
normative principle and the right-holder’s interests. Victims have, as a general rule, an
interest not only in their fate but also in their status, in what can permissibly be done to
them.75 Normatively speaking, the intention to harm is an integral part of the harm itself
(“even a dog knows the difference between being stumbled over and being kicked”). It is
thus justified to define the scope of the right not to be harmed not only according to the
outcome but also according to the manner in which the harm was inflicted, taking into
account the fact that the harm was intended. Inflicting intended harm is a classic example
73

See, e.g., Robert Cryer & A.P. Simester, Iraq and the Use of Force: Do the Side-Effects Justify the
Means?, 7 THEORETICAL INQ. L. 9, 32-33 (2006).
74

75

See, e.g., EYAL ZAMIR & BARAK MEDINA, LAW, ECONOMICS, AND MORALITY 33-40, 60-63 (2010).

Adil Ahmed Haque, Torture, Terror, and the Inversion of Moral Principle, 10 NEW CRIM. L. REV. 613,
634 (2007).

CONSTITUTIONAL LIMITS TO PRIVATIZATION

26

BARAK MEDINA

of what Dan-Cohen referred to as “actions [that] are generally considered to express
disrespect.”76 In contrast, the principle discussed in the second example lacks such a
status. The fact that the decision to harm a person is the result of a discretion employed
by the Executive Branch rather than by the legislature is not an important element in
characterizing the scope of harm inflicted, as it does not have a close enough effect on the
status of the individual and his or her interests. Inflicting harm through an act decided by
the Executive Branch is not “generally considered to express [more] disrespect” than a
similar act decided by parliament. One may even speculate that in some cases the
opposite is true, as the fact that the majority did not explicitly authorize the infringement
may serve as a source of comfort and hope for change.
The question is then to which of the examples the case of privatization is closer. The
importance of answering this question is clear: if a prisoner has a right not to be subject to
the powers of private prison guards using force and other corrective measures against
him, the prohibition against prison privatization becomes almost absolute, and is enforced
through judicial review. It enables the court to enforce the unwritten norm against
privatization by characterizing it as part of the prisoners’ basic rights. On the other hand,
if a prisoner is only entitled not to be subject to the powers of prison guards using force
and other corrective measures against him, the privatization itself does not infringe any
human right, and its legitimacy should be determined on the basis of its specific nature,
including the private prison staff scope of discretion, their required qualifications, the
applicable monitoring properties, and so forth. In such a case, the enforcement of a
general norm against privatization of prisons must be based on a Constitutional provision
(possibly even an implicit one), outside the realm of the Bill of Rights.
To my view, we should distinguish in this respect between the Court’s two reasons
for classifying prison privatization as an infringement of inmates’ basic liberties. The first
reason, which deals with the privatization’s effect on the “democratic legitimacy” of
imposing sanctions, and the state’s obligations under the “social contract,” seems closer
to the second example presented above, regarding the lack of authorization by law. The
76

See supra note 67.

CONSTITUTIONAL LIMITS TO PRIVATIZATION

27

BARAK MEDINA

principle that the state should decide not only on the sanction but also execute it, to
ensure that it “discharges its basic responsibility as sovereign for enforcing the criminal
law and furthering the general public interest,”77 is a principle that deals with the public
interest in general. It is a principle which is remote from the inmate’s interests. It seems
difficult to sustain the view that an inmate having a substantial interest in the sanction
that he or she bears actually “furthers the general public interest,” or conveys some social
message. It is accordingly questionable to assume that the execution of punishment by a
private entity, which thus lacks, arguably, popular legitimacy, expresses some kind of
disrespect toward the inmate.
In contrast, it seems more plausible to accept the Court’s position as far as the second
reason is concerned, which deals with the symbolic status of the inmate. An inmate has,
at least as an objective matter, a substantial interest in being treated as a human being, not
as a mere means for a private corporation to make a profit. If it can be shown that prison
privatization brings about such a (symbolic) outcome, it is indeed justified to classify it as
an independent infringement of inmates’ basic liberties.
This leads to the other aspect of the evaluation of the decision—the position that
privatization as such, regardless of its specific nature, inevitably brings about the
aforementioned symbolic and cultural consequences. In my view, this position is not
sufficiently founded. One aspect is the relatively minor role that private entities play in
shaping the social status of imposing sanctions. As already argued above, the social
meaning of punishment is shaped primarily by the role of the public in deciding on the
sanctions and regulating the prisons, and much less by the identity of the entity that
operates the prison.78 The inmate should not be considered as a mere means for making
profits, since his or her status as an inmate was not determined by the private corporation
but by public organs. The fact that the private corporation gains profits from the inmate’s
sentence is a mere side effect of the criminal court’s decision to impose the sanctions,
clearly not the criminal court’s intended outcome.
77

HCJ 2605/05, supra note 1, para 29 (President Beinisch).

78

Rosky, supra note 22, at 967-68.

CONSTITUTIONAL LIMITS TO PRIVATIZATION

28

BARAK MEDINA

An even more serious difficulty is the Court’s reliance on a seemingly clear-cut
distinction between “private” and “public” actors. Theorists and lawyers alike face
notorious difficulties in their efforts to draw the line between private and public.79 In fact,
there is no clear division, but rather a continuum, between private and public entities.80
According to the prevailing approach, the private-public distinction is normatively
baseless, and is used, if at all, only for descriptive purposes. An activity is “private” if it
is free of limitations, such that the actor is free to employ her discretion regardless of the
interests of others, and it is “public” if the actor is subject to such limitations. The
decision whether an activity should be subject to limitations is based on substantial
reasoning, rather than on some formal, pre-defined classification as “private” or “public.”
The classification is the outcome of the substantive consideration, not its source.
Consequently, it is difficult to make any meaningful distinction between prisons’ staff
according to the formal status of their employer, the state or a private corporation.
On the one hand, prison employees, who are employed by a private corporation, are
far from being “private” in the above sense. As suggested by one commentator,
“privatization can be a means of ‘publicization,’ through which private actors
increasingly commit themselves to traditionally public goals as the price of access to
lucrative opportunities to deliver goods and services that might otherwise be provided
directly by the state.”81 Indeed, as already indicated, according to Israeli law, all
employees of a corporation that operates a prison are formally defined as “civil servants.”
They are legally required to respect prisoners’ rights, and may infringe upon these rights
only as far as the public interest justifies it. In essence, the law does not grant any

79

See, e.g., Duncan Kennedy, The Stages of the Decline of the Public/Private Distinction, 130 U. PA. L.
REV. 1349 (1982); Ruth Gavison, Feminism and the Public/Private Distinction, 45 STAN. L. REV. 1 (1992);
Verkuil, supra note 8, at 402-06.
80

See, e.g., Brentwood Acad. v. Tenn. Secondary Sch. Athletic Ass’n, 531 U.S. 288, 302 (2001); Jody
Freeman, The Private Role in Public Governance, 75 N.Y.U. L. REV. 543, 548 (2000) (arguing that there is
“no purely private realm and no purely public one … [only] the set of negotiated relationships between the
public and the private”).
81

Jody Freeman, Public Values in an Era of Privatization: Extending Public Law Norms through
Privatization, 116 HARV. L. REV. 1285, 1285 (2003). See also Rosky, supra note 22, at 969. See also
Verkuil, supra note 8.

CONSTITUTIONAL LIMITS TO PRIVATIZATION

29

BARAK MEDINA

“freedom” to those who work for a private corporation in comparison to the legal
requirements imposed on a prison-guard who works in a public prison.
At the same time, so-called “public” prison staff do not necessarily act as public in
the legal sense, and thus the assumption that there is a significant difference in the prison
guards’ actual motivations is questionable. Both types of employees work to earn a
living, both are interested in fulfilling their professional goals and developing their
career, and both are interested in the success of their institution.82 Public workers often
earn on the basis of their achievements (for instance, tax collectors must meet collection
quotas), and classifying them as “public” rather than “private” is difficult.83
It thus seems questionable to assume that the public perceptions of the symbolic
meaning of prison privatization are shaped according to a formalistic distinction between
private and public prisons, disregarding the substantial elements of both “public” and
“private” legal norms and actors’ motivations in both types of incarceration facilities.
There may well be a threshold level to a facility’s “privateness,” that is, a level of
freedom left to the prison staff to shape the norms of behavior in the place, which can be
reasonably assumed to bring about the symbolic and social meanings that the Court
attaches to prison privatization. However, it is difficult to sustain the position that any
type of privatization, even one with only marginal elements of “privateness,” should be
assumed to inevitably bring about the above-mentioned symbolic consequences.
Moreover, privatization is spreading, and over time, public perceptions of privatizing the
provision of what used to be considered services provided exclusively by the state may
well change.84 Finally, under the Court’s theory, it is not clear what should be the status
of inmates’ consent to be held in a privatized prison.

82

See, e.g., Lippke, supra note 52, at 34.

83

Id. at 35 (“Prisoners in private facilities may wonder whether what they are compelled to do is for their
own good or is calculated to promote the bottom line of the corporations that own the facilities. In fairness,
similar questions may arise within public prisons, since state-employed prison administrators and guards
have interests of their own to protect.”); Rosky, supra note 22, at 969.
84

Rosky, supra note 22, at 967-68.

CONSTITUTIONAL LIMITS TO PRIVATIZATION

30

BARAK MEDINA

Consequently, I don’t think that we should view incidents of the use of force by a
prison-guard against a prisoner as “actions [that] are generally considered to express
disrespect” just because the prison staff works for a corporation rather than the state. I
agree that privatization is an important element in evaluating the legitimacy of taking
measures against inmates, not only in terms of the actual risk of misuse of power by the
“private” prison guards as compared to “public” ones, but also in terms of the concern
that operating a for-profit prison will convey a message of disrespect to inmates.
However, such suppositions cannot be made in the abstract, based solely on the formal
status of the entity that operates the prison as a private one. It is essential to inquire what
risks of abuse of power and symbolic disrespect can be reasonably assumed given the
concrete details of the legislation under consideration. Some forms of prison privatization
may well be classified as an infringement of inmates’ rights to human dignity, as a result
of the social message that they convey, but others may not. It thus seems that one may
(partially) agree with the Court’s principled approach, that prison privatization may
infringe upon liberty and human dignity, but also question the view that such a
conclusion is inevitable.

IV. THE ROAD UNTAKEN: DIRECT ENFORCEMENT OF A CONSTITUTIONAL
PROHIBITION AGAINST PRISON PRIVATIZATION
There are two main legal routes to deal with the privatization of prisons, as well as
other forms of governmental use of force. One path is the one accepted in almost all
Western democracies—instead of fighting against privatization, working to “publicize”
the applicable norms.85 Privatization does not entail deregulation; to the contrary,
privatization may lead to the demand of greater public accountability from the private
entities that are empowered to implement governmental powers, as well as from those
public offices that are in charge of guiding these entities and supervising them.86 This
85
86

Freeman, supra note 81.

See, e.g., Martha Minow, Public and Private Partnerships: Accounting for the New Religion, 116 Harv.
L. Rev. 1229, 1236-37 (2003) (“Whatever the normative limitations of the arguments favoring public-

CONSTITUTIONAL LIMITS TO PRIVATIZATION

31

BARAK MEDINA

route includes heightened judicial scrutiny to prevent the violation of inmates’ basic
rights. Such scrutiny may well result in not only invalidating specific actions taken by a
private corporation or requiring it to compensate those who were subject to its misuse of
force, but also in a review of the activities of the supervising authorities. Moreover, in
appropriate circumstances, when a repeated practice of human rights violation is evident,
there may be a basis for invalidating the privatization itself.
As mentioned above, the Israeli Supreme Court has taken this path for the last three
decades. However, the recent decision marks a choice of an alternative route, based on
the presumption that (at least certain types of) privatization are invalid per se, as an apriori matter. It seems, however, that this position requires the recognition of a
Constitutional norm, which prohibits the privatization of certain governmental powers.
The focal point of such a norm is not in protecting the interests (“human rights”) of the
specific individuals who are subject to the use of force by the private entity, but in
enforcing a norm for the separation of powers in a liberal society. In its decision, the
Israeli Supreme Court briefly addressed the possibility of identifying such a
Constitutional norm that prohibits privatization of certain powers. In this respect, the
Court referred to Article 1 of the Basic-Law: The Government, which states that “the
Government is the Executive Branch of the State.” The Court stated that this provision
may well be interpreted as prohibiting certain forms of privatization:87
“Article 1 of the Basic-Law: the Government does not expressly
determine specific duties or spheres of activity where the government has an
exclusive responsibility to act. Notwithstanding ...and especially in view of
our outlook concerning the broad interpretation that should be given to
provisions that have a constitutional status, we are inclined to interpret
[Article 1] in a manner that enshrines on a constitutional level the existence of
a ‘hard core’ of sovereign powers that the government as the executive
private partnerships, the trend is undeniable. State, local, and federal governments are widely exploring
privatization. Skeptics should not simply decry this reality, but deal with it by demanding public
accountability.”).
87

HCJ 2605/05, supra note 1, para 63 (President Beinisch).

CONSTITUTIONAL LIMITS TO PRIVATIZATION

32

BARAK MEDINA

branch is liable to exercise itself and that it may not transfer or delegate to
private enterprises. …[T]he powers involved in the imprisonment of
offenders and in the use of organized force on behalf of the state are indeed
included within this ‘hard core.’”
As indicated above, the Court also referred extensively to the concept of “social
contract” in identifying a general prohibition against the privatization of the power to use
force.88
However, the Court decided not to base its decision on Article 1 or to explicitly
identify an enforceable Constitutional norm against privatization, outside the realm of
human rights law. The Court reasoned that interpreting Article 1 as prohibiting certain
types of privatizations, or identifying such a general norm, would require the Court “to
clearly define the limits of that ‘hard core’ [of sovereign powers that the government may
not delegate to private entities], since it may be assumed that there is no constitutional
impediment to privatization of the vast majority of services provided by the state, and this
matter lies mainly within the scope of the discretion of the legislative and executive
branches.”89 The Court states that it is preferable to avoid making such a principled
decision by the judiciary, and in the absence of an explicit Constitutional provision the
Court should delineate this prohibition on a case-to-case basis.90
It seems that the Court’s main concern was that explicitly identifying such a
prohibition against privatization outside the realm of the Bill of Rights would lack
sufficient …“democratic legitimacy.” As indicated at the outset, since the “Constitutional
Revolution” of 1995, the Israeli Supreme Court has not struck down legislation on the
basis of its incompatibility with provisions of Basic-Laws other than those protecting
human rights. An expansive interpretation of Article 1 of the Basic-Law: the Government

88

See supra note 62.

89

HCJ 2605/05, supra note 1, para 63 (President Beinisch). See also id, para 3-4 (Justice Hayut).

90

Id. para 65 (President Beinisch). The Court also pointed out that unlike the Basic-Law: Human Dignity
and Liberty, which includes a “Limitation Clause” that determines the conditions in which a human right
can be justifiably infringed, the Basic-Law: the Government does not include such a clause, and it is not
clear in what terms, if at all, the government may privatize “hard core” powers. Id. para 63.

CONSTITUTIONAL LIMITS TO PRIVATIZATION

33

BARAK MEDINA

might have been perceived as invalidating legislation on the basis of “unwritten norms,” a
move which is highly controversial.
It seems that the Israeli Supreme Court’s decision in this case aimed at having the
cake and eating it too: It aimed at maintaining popular legitimacy of a judicial review of
legislation by presenting it as based on the enforcement of a “written” provision of the
Israeli Constitution, of prisoners’ rights to liberty and human dignity. In fact, the norm
that was enforced lay beyond the scope of the Bill of Rights and is actually an unwritten
one. Indeed, few of the Justices explicitly acknowledged the possibility that the
expansion of the scope of the rights to liberty and human dignity, to include an
independent right against privatization, amounts to an enforcement of an unwritten
norm.91 As a political matter, this move can be praised, as it enabled the court to “save”
the country from a policy that may well be wrong.92 Nevertheless, from the perspective of
legal theory, it seems that given its position that the privatization of the use of force is
prohibited, the Court should have identified explicitly such a Constitutional norm, rather
than expanding the scope of rights to liberty and human dignity.

91

Id. (Vice-president Rivlin) (“The violation involved in the arrangement undermines the very structure of
the democratic constitution. It is also possible to hold that we are dealing with a violation that exceeds the
scope of the Basic-Laws, and lies in the field of the social contract upon which the existence of the state is
founded. Releasing the state from the monopoly granted to it with regard to the use of force in order to
protect the public interest undermines the principles upon which the entire social and constitutional
foundations of the state rest.”); id. para 17-20 (Justice Levy, dissent); id. para 3-4 (Justice Hayut); id. para
29 (Justice Naor).
92

Somewhat surprisingly, given the often critical reaction in the Israeli popular discourse regarding
Supreme Court decisions that invalidate legislation, the decision was supported by almost all commentators
and politicians.